•  127
    The evidential support theory of conditionals
    Synthese 164 (1): 19-44. 2008.
    According to so-called epistemic theories of conditionals, the assertability/acceptability/acceptance of a conditional requires the existence of an epistemically significant relation between the conditional’s antecedent and its consequent. This paper points to some linguistic data that our current best theories of the foregoing type appear unable to explain. Further, it presents a new theory of the same type that does not have that shortcoming. The theory is then defended against some seemingly …Read more
  •  45
    Learning Conditional Information
    Mind and Language 27 (3): 239-263. 2012.
    Some of the information we receive comes to us in an explicitly conditional form. It is an open question how to model the accommodation of such information in a Bayesian framework. This paper presents data suggesting that there may be no strictly Bayesian account of updating on conditionals. Specifically, the data seem to indicate that such updating at least sometimes proceeds on the basis of explanatory considerations, which famously have no home in standard Bayesian epistemology. The paper als…Read more
  •  19
  •  116
    Inference to the Best Explanation versus Bayes’s Rule in a Social Setting
    with Sylvia Wenmackers
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 68 (2). 2017.
    This article compares inference to the best explanation with Bayes’s rule in a social setting, specifically, in the context of a variant of the Hegselmann–Krause model in which agents not only update their belief states on the basis of evidence they receive directly from the world, but also take into account the belief states of their fellow agents. So far, the update rules mentioned have been studied only in an individualistic setting, and it is known that in such a setting both have their stre…Read more
  •  66
    Over recent decades, computer simulations have become a common tool among practitioners of the social sciences. They have been utilized to study such diverse phenomena as the integration and segregation of different racial groups, the emergence and evolution of friendship networks, the spread of gossip, fluctuations of housing prices in an area, the transmission of social norms, and many more. Philosophers of science and others interested in the methodological status of these studies have identi…Read more
  •  172
    Putnam’s Model-Theoretic Argument Reconstructed
    Journal of Philosophy 96 (9): 479-490. 1999.
    Putnam's model theoretic argument against metaphysical realism can be reconstructed as valid, with premises acceptable to the realist. There is no illegitimate assumption that the causal theory of reference is false.
  •  293
    Testing Inference To The Best Explanation
    Synthese 130 (3): 355-377. 2002.
    Inference to the Best Explanation has become the subject of a livelydebate in the philosophy of science. Scientific realists maintain, while scientificantirealists deny, that it is a compelling rule of inference. It seems that anyattempt to settle this debate empirically must beg the question against theantirealist. The present paper argues that this impression is misleading. A methodis described that, by combining Glymour's theory of bootstrapping and Hacking'sarguments from microscopy, allows …Read more
  •  50
    Marc Slors on personal identity
    Philosophical Explorations 2 (2). 1999.
    Theories of personal identity purport to specify truth conditions for sentences of the form 'x-at-ti is the same person as y-at-tj. Most philosophers nowadays agree that such truth conditions are to be stated in terms of psychological continuity. However; opinions vary as to how the notion of psychological continuity is to be understood. In a recent contribution to this journal, Slors offers an account in which psychological continuity is spelled out in terms of narrative connectedness between m…Read more
  •  35
    1. The Epistemology of Conditionals
    Oxford Studies in Epistemology 4 1. 2013.
  •  29
    Lotteries, Knowledge, and Rational Belief: Essays on the Lottery Paradox (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 2020.
    We talk and think about our beliefs both in a categorical and in a graded way. How do the two kinds of belief hang together? The most straightforward answer is that we believe something categorically if we believe it to a high enough degree. But this seemingly obvious, near-platitudinous claim is known to give rise to a paradox commonly known as the 'lottery paradox' – at least when it is coupled with some further seeming near-platitudes about belief. How to resolve that paradox has been a matte…Read more
  •  92
    Simulating peer disagreements
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 41 (2): 148-157. 2010.
    It has been claimed that epistemic peers, upon discovering that they disagree on some issue, should give up their opposing views and ‘split the difference’. The present paper challenges this claim by showing, with the help of computer simulations, that what the rational response to the discovery of peer disagreement is—whether it is sticking to one’s belief or splitting the difference—depends on factors that are contingent and highly context-sensitive.Keywords: Peer disagreement; Computer simula…Read more
  •  221
    Inference to the best explanation made coherent
    Philosophy of Science 66 (Supplement). 1999.
    Van Fraassen (1989) argues that Inference to the Best Explanation is incoherent in the sense that adopting it as a rule for belief change will make one susceptible to a dynamic Dutch book. The present paper argues against this. A strategy is described that allows us to infer to the best explanation free of charge
  •  110
    Probabilist antirealism
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 91 (1): 38-63. 2010.
    Until now, antirealists have offered sketches of a theory of truth, at best. In this paper, we present a probabilist account of antirealist truth in some formal detail, and we assess its ability to deal with the problems that are standardly taken to beset antirealism.
  •  18
    Two accounts of similarity compared
    In Hieke Alexander & Leitgeb Hannes (eds.), Reduction, Abstraction, Analysis, Ontos Verlag. pp. 387--389. 2009.
  •  80
    Decision theory and the rationality of further deliberation
    Economics and Philosophy 18 (2): 303-328. 2002.
    Bayesian decision theory operates under the fiction that in any decision-making situation the agent is simply given the options from which he is to choose. It thereby sets aside some characteristics of the decision-making situation that are pre-analytically of vital concern to the verdict on the agent's eventual decision. In this paper it is shown that and how these characteristics can be accommodated within a still recognizably Bayesian account of rational agency.
  •  149
    A Pragmatic Dissolution of Harman’s Paradox
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74 (2): 326-345. 2007.
    There is widespread agreement that we cannot know of a lottery ticket we own that it is a loser prior to the drawing of the lottery. At the same time we appear to have knowledge of events that will occur only if our ticket is a loser. Supposing any plausible closure principle for knowledge, the foregoing seems to yield a paradox. Appealing to some broadly Gricean insights, the present paper argues that this paradox is apparent only.
  •  162
    Assertion, Moore, and Bayes
    Philosophical Studies 144 (3): 361-375. 2009.
    It is widely believed that the so-called knowledge account of assertion best explains why sentences such as “It’s raining in Paris but I don’t believe it” and “It’s raining in Paris but I don’t know it” appear odd to us. I argue that the rival rational credibility account of assertion explains that fact just as well. I do so by providing a broadly Bayesian analysis of the said type of sentences which shows that such sentences cannot express rationally held beliefs. As an interesting aside, it wi…Read more
  • Grondslagen en toepassingen van de formele epistemologie
    Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 101 (4): 237-244. 2009.
  •  271
    A contextualist solution to the Gettier problem
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 69 (1): 207-228. 2005.
    According to the deontological view on justification, being justified in believing some proposition is a matter of having done one's epistemic duty with respect to that proposition. The present paper argues that, given a proper articulation of the deontological view, it is defensible that knowledge is justified true belief, pace virtually all epistemologists since Gettier. One important claim to be argued for is that once it is appreciated that it depends on contextual factors whether a person h…Read more
  • Empiricist Semantics and Indeterminism of Reference
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 70 171-188. 2000.
  •  98
    Can the World Help Us in Fixing the Reference of Natural Kind Terms?
    Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 29 (1). 1998.
    According to Putnam the reference of natural kind terms is fixed by the world, at least partly; whether two things belong to the same kind depends on whether they obey the same objective laws. We show that Putnam's criterion of substance identity only "works" if we read "objective laws" as "OBJECTIVE LAWS". Moreover, at least some of the laws of some of the special sciences have to be included. But what we consider to be good special sciences and what not depends upon our values. Hence, "objecti…Read more
  •  23
    Basic Beliefs, Coherence, and Bootstrap Confirmation
    In Rene van Woudenberg, Sabine Roeser & Ron Rood (eds.), Basic Belief and Basic Knowledge, Ontos-verlag. pp. 4--57. 2005.
  •  17
    A Paradox for Empiricism
    Philosophy of Science 63 (5). 1996.
    According to van Fraassen, constructive empiricism yields a better account of science than does scientific realism. One particularly important advantage van Fraassen claims his position to have over scientific realism is that the former can make sense of science without invoking pre-Kantian metaphysics. In the present paper the consistency of van Fraassen's position is put in doubt. Specifically, it will be argued that van Fraassen faces the paradox that he cannot do with nor without the pre-Kan…Read more
  •  18
    Indicatives, concessives, and evidential support
    with Sara Verbrugge
    Thinking and Reasoning 18 (4): 480-499. 2012.
  •  368
    Assertion, knowledge, and rational credibility
    Philosophical Review 115 (4): 449-485. 2006.
  •  14
    Empirische toetsing Van inductieve logica's
    Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 62 (4). 2000.
    Inductive logics purport to specify, for any given hypothesis and any given evidence statement, whether and, if so, to what extent the evidence statement should bear on our confidence that the hypothesis is true. If we agree that there can only be one true answer to questions of this sort, then the project of inductive logic faces a serious difficulty, namely that the many different systems that have been proposed in the literature rarely reach an unanimous verdict. In this paper I investigate t…Read more
  •  430
    Ramsey’s test, adams’ thesis, and left-nested conditionals
    Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (3): 467-484. 2010.
    Adams famously suggested that the acceptability of any indicative conditional whose antecedent and consequent are both factive sentences amounts to the subjective conditional probability of the consequent given the antecedent. The received view has it that this thesis offers an adequate partial explication of Ramsey’s test, which characterizes graded acceptability for conditionals in terms of hypothetical updates on the antecedent. Some results in van Fraassen may raise hope that this explicator…Read more