•  36
    Fairness versus Doing the Most Good
    Hastings Center Report 24 (4): 36-39. 1994.
  •  55
    Trump and Climate Change
    The Philosophers' Magazine 76 22-22. 2017.
  •  463
    Does Rationality Consist in Responding Correctly to Reasons?
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 4 (3): 349-374. 2007.
    Some philosophers think that rationality consists in responding correctly to reasons, or alternatively in responding correctly to beliefs about reasons. This paper considers various possible interpretations of ‘responding correctly to reasons’ and of ‘responding correctly to beliefs about reasons’, and concludes that rationality consists in neither, under any interpretation. It recognizes that, under some interpretations, rationality does entail responding correctly to beliefs about reasons. Tha…Read more
  •  72
    Responses to Setiya, Hussain, and Horty
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 91 (1): 230-242. 2015.
  •  141
    Are intentions reasons? And how should we cope with incommensurable values
    In Christopher W. Morris & Arthur Ripstein (eds.), Practical Rationality and Preference: Essays for David Gauthier, Cambridge University Press. pp. 98--120. 2001.
  •  332
    Reasons and motivation: John Broome
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 71 (1). 1997.
    Derek Parfit takes an externalist and cognitivist view about normative reasons. I shall explore this view and add some arguments that support it. But I shall also raise a doubt about it at the end.
  •  382
    "Utility"
    Economics and Philosophy 7 (1): 1-12. 1991.
    “Utility,” in plain English, means usefulness. In Australia, a ute is a useful vehicle. Jeremy Bentham specialized the meaning to a particular sort of usefulness. “By utility,” he said, “is meant that property in any object, whereby it tends to produce benefit, advantage, pleasure, good, or happiness or to prevent the happening of mischief, pain, evil, or unhappiness to the party whose interest is considered”. The “principle of utility” is the principle that actions are to be judged by their use…Read more
  •  865
    Normative requirements
    Ratio 12 (4). 1999.
    Normative requirements are often overlooked, but they are central features of the normative world. Rationality is often thought to consist in acting for reasons, but following normative requirements is also a major part of rationality. In particular, correct reasoning – both theoretical and practical – is governed by normative requirements rather than by reasons. This article explains the nature of normative requirements, and gives examples of their importance. It also describes mistakes that ph…Read more
  •  186
    Weighing lives
    Oxford University Press. 2004.
    We are often faced with choices that involve the weighing of people's lives against each other, or the weighing of lives against other good things. These are choices both for individuals and for societies. A person who is terminally ill may have to choose between palliative care and more aggressive treatment, which will give her a longer life but at some cost in suffering. We have to choose between the convenience to ourselves of road and air travel, and the lives of the future people who will b…Read more
  •  453
    A world climate bank
    with Duncan Foley
    In Iñigo González-Ricoy & Axel Gosseries (eds.), Institutions for Future Generations, Oxford University Press Uk. pp. 156-169. 2016.
  •  305
    Instrumental reasoning
    In Julian Nida-Rümelin & Wolfgang Spohn (eds.), Rationality, Rules and Structure, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 195-207. 2000.
    Like all reasoning, practical reasoning is a process that takes a person from some of her existing mental states to a new mental state. Theoretical reasoning concludes in a belief; practical reasoning in an intention. This paper concentrates on instrumental reasoning, a species of practical reasoning in general. It argues that instrumental reasoning is correct if the content of the reasoning is a valid derivation, just as theoretical reasoning is correct if its content is a valid derivation. It …Read more
  •  213
  •  91
    Ethics Out of Economics
    Cambridge University Press. 1999.
    Many economic problems are also ethical problems: should we value economic equality? how much should we care about preserving the environment? how should medical resources be divided between saving life and enhancing life? This book examines some of the practical issues that lie between economics and ethics, and shows how utility theory can contribute to ethics. John Broome's work has, unusually, combined sophisticated economic and philosophical expertise, and Ethics Out of Economics brings toge…Read more
  •  287
    Structured and Unstructured Valuation
    Analyse & Kritik 16 (2): 121-132. 1994.
    Economists can value things for cost-benefit analysis using either a structured or an unstructured approach. The first imposes some theoretical structure on the valuation; the second does not. This paper explains the difference between the approaches and examines the relative merits of each. Cost-benefit analysis may be aimed at finding what would be the best action, or alternatively at finding which action should be done in a democracy. The paper explains the difference, and argues that the app…Read more
  •  39
    Reply to Qizilbash
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (1). 2007.
  •  51
    Replies
    Economics and Philosophy 23 (1): 115-124. 2007.
    I am extremely grateful to the five commentators for readingmy book and offering such interesting thoughts in reaction. Shortage of space may make my responses seem brusque. But of course they are not meant to be.
  •  269
  •  117
    Dorsey rejects Conclusion, so he believes he must reject one of the premises. He argues that the best option is to reject Premise 3. Rejecting Premise 3 entails a certain sort of discontinuity in value. So Dorsey believes he has an argument for discontinuity
  •  1
  •  71
    Have we reason to do as rationality requires? - a comment on Raz
    Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 1 (Symposium): 1-10. 2005.
    No abstract
  •  40
    The mutual determination of wants and benefits
    Theory and Decision 37 (3): 333-338. 1994.
  •  5
    Some words of greeting
    Economics and Philosophy 11 (1). 1995.
  •  33
    Précis
    Philosophical Studies 173 (12): 3369-3371. 2016.
  •  550
    Wide or narrow scope?
    Mind 116 (462): 359-370. 2007.
    This paper is a response to ‘Why Be Rational?’ by Niko Kolodny. Kolodny argues that we have no reason to satisfy the requirements of rationality. His argument assumes that these requirements have a logically narrow scope. To see what the question of scope turns on, this comment provides a semantics for ‘requirement’. It shows that requirements of rationality have a wide scope, at least under one sense of ‘requirement’. Consequently Kolodny's conclusion cannot be derived.