•  5
    Some words of greeting
    Economics and Philosophy 11 (1). 1995.
  •  432
    Climate change: life and death
    In Jeremy Moss (ed.), Climate Change and Justice, Cambridge University Press. 2015.
    commissioned for the Stern Review of the Economics of Climate Change.
  •  33
    Précis
    Philosophical Studies 173 (12): 3369-3371. 2016.
  •  548
    Wide or narrow scope?
    Mind 116 (462): 359-370. 2007.
    This paper is a response to ‘Why Be Rational?’ by Niko Kolodny. Kolodny argues that we have no reason to satisfy the requirements of rationality. His argument assumes that these requirements have a logically narrow scope. To see what the question of scope turns on, this comment provides a semantics for ‘requirement’. It shows that requirements of rationality have a wide scope, at least under one sense of ‘requirement’. Consequently Kolodny's conclusion cannot be derived.
  •  375
    Is Rationality Normative?
    Disputatio 2 (23): 161-178. 2007.
    Rationality requires various things of you. For example, it requires you not to have contradictory beliefs, and to intend what you believe is a necessary means to an end that you intend. Suppose rationality requires you to F. Does this fact constitute a reason for you to F? Does it even follow from this fact that you have a reason to F? I examine these questions and reach a sceptical conclusion about them. I can find no satisfactory argument to show that either has the answer ‘yes’. I consider t…Read more
  •  6
    The Value of a Person
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 68 (1): 167-198. 1994.
  •  171
    Equality versus priority: A useful distinction
    Economics and Philosophy 31 (2): 219-228. 2015.
    :Both egalitarianism and prioritarianism give value to equality. Prioritarianism has an additively separable value function whereas egalitarianism does not. I show that in some cases prioritarianism and egalitarianism necessarily have different implications: I describe two alternatives G and H such that egalitarianism necessarily implies G is better than H whereas prioritarianism necessarily implies G and H are equally good. I also raise a doubt about the intelligibility of prioritarianism.
  •  457
    Esteemed philosopher John Broome avoids the familiar ideological stances on climate change policy and examines the issue through an invigorating new lens. As he considers the moral dimensions of climate change, he reasons clearly through what universal standards of goodness and justice require of us, both as citizens and as governments. His conclusions—some as demanding as they are logical—will challenge and enlighten. Eco-conscious readers may be surprised to hear they have a duty to offset all…Read more
  •  675
    The badness of death and the goodness of life
    In Fred Feldman, Ben Bradley & Jens Johansson (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Death, Oxford University Press. 2012.
  •  73
    Reasons
    In R. Jay Wallace (ed.), Reason and value: themes from the moral philosophy of Joseph Raz, Oxford University Press. pp. 2004--28. 2004.
  •  159
    Normativity in Reasoning
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 95 (4): 622-633. 2014.
    Reasoning is a process through which premise-attitudes give rise to a conclusion-attitude. When you reason actively you operate on the propositions that are the contents of your premise-attitudes, following a rule, to derive a new proposition that is the content of your conclusion-attitude. It may seem that, when you follow a rule, you must, at least implicitly, have the normative belief that you ought to comply with the rule, which guides you to comply. But I argue that to follow a rule is to m…Read more
  •  45
    V*—Fairness
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91 (1): 87-102. 1991.
    John Broome; V*—Fairness, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 91, Issue 1, 1 June 1991, Pages 87–102, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/91.1.87.
  •  141
    Indefiniteness in Identity
    Analysis 44 (1). 1984.
  •  224
    The most important thing about climate change
    In Jonathan Boston, Andrew Bradstock & David L. Eng (eds.), Public policy: why ethics matters, Anue Press. pp. 101-16. 2010.
    This book chapter is not available in ORA, but you may download, display, print and reproduce this chapter in unaltered form only for your personal, non-commercial use or use within your organization from the ANU E Press website.
  •  1295
  •  51
    Reply to Vallentyne
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 78 (3): 747-752. 2009.
    No Abstract
  •  58
  •  5
    Representing an ordering when the population varies
    Social Choice and Welfare 20 243-6. 2003.
    This note describes a domain of distributions of wellbeing, in which different distributions may have different populations. It proves a representation theorem for an ordering defined on this domain.
  •  303
    Do not ask for morality
    In Adrian Walsh, Säde Hormio & Duncan Purves (eds.), The Ethical Underpinnings of Climate Economics, Routledge. pp. 9-21. 2016.
  •  55
    Précis of Rationality Through Reasoning
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 91 (1): 200-203. 2015.
  •  25
    A Reply to Sen
    Economics and Philosophy 7 (2): 285. 1991.
  •  521
    Incommensurable values
    In Roger Crisp & Brad Hooker (eds.), Well-Being and Morality: Essays in Honour of James Griffin, Clarendon Press. pp. 21--38. 2000.
    Two options are incommensurate in value if neither is better than the other, and if a small improvement or worsening of one does not necessarily make it determinately better or worse than the other. If a person faces a sequence of choices between incommensurate options, she may end up with a worse options than she could have had, even though none of her choices are irrational. Yet it seems that rationality should save her from this bad outcome. This is the practical problem posed by incommensura…Read more
  •  35
    The welfare economics of population
    Social Choice and Welfare 2 221-34. 1985.
    Intuition suggests there is no value in adding people to the population if it brings no benefits to people already living: creating people is morally neutral in itself. This paper examines the difficulties of incorporating this intuition into a coherent theory of the value of population. It takes three existing theories within welfare economics - average utilitarianism, relativist utilitarianism, and critical-level utilitarianism - and considers whether they can satisfactorily accommodate the in…Read more
  •  291
    Fairness
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91. 1991.
    John Broome; V*—Fairness, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 91, Issue 1, 1 June 1991, Pages 87–102, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/91.1.87.