•  675
    The badness of death and the goodness of life
    In Fred Feldman, Ben Bradley & Jens Johansson (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Death, Oxford University Press. 2012.
  •  73
    Reasons
    In R. Jay Wallace (ed.), Reason and value: themes from the moral philosophy of Joseph Raz, Oxford University Press. pp. 2004--28. 2004.
  •  45
    V*—Fairness
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91 (1): 87-102. 1991.
    John Broome; V*—Fairness, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 91, Issue 1, 1 June 1991, Pages 87–102, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/91.1.87.
  •  159
    Normativity in Reasoning
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 95 (4): 622-633. 2014.
    Reasoning is a process through which premise-attitudes give rise to a conclusion-attitude. When you reason actively you operate on the propositions that are the contents of your premise-attitudes, following a rule, to derive a new proposition that is the content of your conclusion-attitude. It may seem that, when you follow a rule, you must, at least implicitly, have the normative belief that you ought to comply with the rule, which guides you to comply. But I argue that to follow a rule is to m…Read more
  •  141
    Indefiniteness in Identity
    Analysis 44 (1). 1984.
  •  224
    The most important thing about climate change
    In Jonathan Boston, Andrew Bradstock & David L. Eng (eds.), Public policy: why ethics matters, Anue Press. pp. 101-16. 2010.
    This book chapter is not available in ORA, but you may download, display, print and reproduce this chapter in unaltered form only for your personal, non-commercial use or use within your organization from the ANU E Press website.
  •  1295
  •  51
    Reply to Vallentyne
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 78 (3): 747-752. 2009.
    No Abstract
  •  58
  •  5
    Representing an ordering when the population varies
    Social Choice and Welfare 20 243-6. 2003.
    This note describes a domain of distributions of wellbeing, in which different distributions may have different populations. It proves a representation theorem for an ordering defined on this domain.
  •  25
    A Reply to Sen
    Economics and Philosophy 7 (2): 285. 1991.
  •  303
    Do not ask for morality
    In Adrian Walsh, Säde Hormio & Duncan Purves (eds.), The Ethical Underpinnings of Climate Economics, Routledge. pp. 9-21. 2016.
  •  55
    Précis of Rationality Through Reasoning
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 91 (1): 200-203. 2015.
  •  35
    The welfare economics of population
    Social Choice and Welfare 2 221-34. 1985.
    Intuition suggests there is no value in adding people to the population if it brings no benefits to people already living: creating people is morally neutral in itself. This paper examines the difficulties of incorporating this intuition into a coherent theory of the value of population. It takes three existing theories within welfare economics - average utilitarianism, relativist utilitarianism, and critical-level utilitarianism - and considers whether they can satisfactorily accommodate the in…Read more
  •  521
    Incommensurable values
    In Roger Crisp & Brad Hooker (eds.), Well-Being and Morality: Essays in Honour of James Griffin, Clarendon Press. pp. 21--38. 2000.
    Two options are incommensurate in value if neither is better than the other, and if a small improvement or worsening of one does not necessarily make it determinately better or worse than the other. If a person faces a sequence of choices between incommensurate options, she may end up with a worse options than she could have had, even though none of her choices are irrational. Yet it seems that rationality should save her from this bad outcome. This is the practical problem posed by incommensura…Read more
  •  291
    Fairness
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91. 1991.
    John Broome; V*—Fairness, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 91, Issue 1, 1 June 1991, Pages 87–102, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/91.1.87.
  •  83
    Synchronic requirements and diachronic permissions
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 45 (5-6): 630-646. 2015.
    Reasoning is an activity of ours by which we come to satisfy synchronic requirements of rationality. However, reasoning itself is regulated by diachronic permissions of rationality. For each synchronic requirement there appears to be a corresponding diachronic permission, but the requirements and permissions are not related to each other in a systematic way. It is therefore a puzzle how reasoning according to permissions can systematically bring us to satisfy requirements
  •  319
    Comments on Boghossian
    Philosophical Studies 169 (1): 19-25. 2014.
  •  97
    Reply to Rabinowicz
    Philosophical Issues 19 (1): 412-417. 2009.
    No Abstract
  •  72
    Should Social Preferences Be Consistent?
    Economics and Philosophy 5 (1): 7. 1989.
    Should social preferences conform to the principles of rationality we normally expect of individuals? Should they, for instance, conform to the consistency axioms of expected utility theory? This article considers one fragment of this question
  •  82
  •  43
    Responses
    Philosophical Studies 173 (12): 3431-3448. 2016.
    This is a response to the comments of Boghossian, Cullity, Pettit and Southwood on my book Rationality Through Reasoning.
  •  369
    This study uses techniques from economics to illuminate fundamental questions in ethics, particularly in the foundations of utilitarianism. Topics considered include the nature of teleological ethics, the foundations of decision theory, the value of equality and the moral significance of a person's continuing identity through time.
  •  266
    Normative practical reasoning: John Broome
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 75 (1). 2001.
    Practical reasoning is a process of reasoning that concludes in an intention. One example is reasoning from intending an end to intending what you believe is a necessary means: 'I will leave the next buoy to port; in order to do that I must tack; so I'll tack', where the first and third sentences express intentions and the second sentence a belief. This sort of practical reasoning is supported by a valid logical derivation, and therefore seems uncontrovertible. A more contentious example is norm…Read more
  •  91
    The Public and Private Morality of Climate Change
    The Tanner Lectures on Human Values 32 3-20. 2013.
    The Tanner Lectures are a collection of educational and scientific discussions relating to human values. Conducted by leaders in their fields, the lectures are presented at prestigious educational facilities around the world
  •  127
    Enkrasia
    Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 20 (4): 425-436. 2013.
  •  251
    Reasoning with preferences?
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 59 183-208. 2006.
    Rationality requires certain things of you. It requires you not to have contradictory beliefs or intentions, not to intend something you believe to be impossible, to believe what obviously follows from something you believe, and so on. Its requirements can be expressed using schemata such as
  •  66
    A Reply To My Critics
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 40 (1): 158-171. 2016.
  •  28
    Reply to Jones-Lee
    Economics and Philosophy 23 (3): 385-387. 2007.
    It is not the job of philosophy to give direct practical advice either to people or to governments. Nevertheless, moral philosophy is immensely significant in practical matters. It influences the way we think and act, but only slowly as it filters through the process of public debate. I hope Weighing Lives will have a practical influence, but it is not meant to be a directly practical guide