•  702
    The Value of a Person
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 68 (1). 1994.
    (for Adam Morton's half) I argue that if we take the values of persons to be ordered in a way that allows incomparability, then the problems Broome raises have easy solutions. In particular we can maintain that creating people is morally neutral while killing them has a negative value.
  •  180
    Reason versus ought
    Philosophical Issues 25 (1): 80-97. 2015.
  •  136
    Normative Practical Reasoning
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 75 (1). 2001.
    Practical reasoning is a process of reasoning that concludes in an intention. One example is reasoning from intending an end to intending what you believe is a necessary means: 'I will leave the next buoy to port; in order to do that I must tack; so I'll tack', where the first and third sentences express intentions and the second sentence a belief. This sort of practical reasoning is supported by a valid logical derivation, and therefore seems uncontrovertible. A more contentious example is norm…Read more
  •  160
    More pain or less?
    Analysis 56 (2): 116-118. 1996.
  •  79
    Jean E. Hampton (1954-1996). Obituary
    with Christopher W. Morris and Philippe Mongin
    Economics and Philosophy 12 (2): 251-252. 1996.
    An obituary of Jean E. Hampton (1954-1996) by the editors of Economics and Philosophy. At the time of her premature death, Jean was serving as a member of the Editorial Board of the journal.
  •  348
    A philosopher at the IPCC
    The Philosophers' Magazine 66 11-16. 2014.
  •  98
    Kamm on Fairness (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (4): 955. 1998.
  •  289
    This chapter surveys some of the issues that arise in policy making when the wellbeing of future generations must be taken into account. It analyses the discounting of future wellbeing, and considers whether it is permissible. It argues that the effects of policy on the number of future people should not be ignored, and it considers what is an appropriate basis for setting a value on these effects. It considers the implications of the non-identity effect for intergenerational justice and for the…Read more
  •  3089
    Since the last ice age, when ice enveloped most of the northern continents, the earth has warmed by about five degrees. Within a century, it is likely to warm by another four or five. This revolution in our climate will have immense and mostly harmful effects on the lives of people not yet born. We are inflicting this harm on our descendants by dumping greenhouse gases into the atmosphere. We can mitigate the harm a little by taking measures to control our emissions of these gases, and to adapt …Read more
  •  145
    The value of living longer
    In Sudhir Anand, Fabienne Peter & Amartya Sen (eds.), Public Health, Ethics, and Equity, Oxford University Press. pp. 243--260. 2004.
  •  140
    Practical reasoning
    In José Luis Bermúdez & Alan Millar (eds.), Reason and Nature: Essays in the Theory of Rationality, Oxford University Press. pp. 85--111. 2002.
  •  234
    Williams on Ought
    In Ulrike Heuer & Gerald R. Lang (eds.), Luck, Value, and Commitment: Themes From the Ethics of Bernard Williams, Oxford University Press, Usa. 2012.
    In 2002, Bernard Williams delivered a lecture that revisited the arguments of his article 'Ought and moral obligation', published in his Moral Luck. The lecture attributed to the earlier article the thesis that there are no ‘personal’ or (as I put it) ‘owned’ oughts. It also rejected this thesis. This paper explains the idea of an owned ought, and supports Williams’s lecture in asserting that there are owned oughts. It also examines the question of how accurately Williams’s later lecture interpr…Read more
  •  89
    The unity of reasoning
    In Simon Robertson (ed.), Spheres of Reason, Oxford University Press. 2009.
  •  255
    Should We Value Population?
    Journal of Political Philosophy 13 (4): 399-413. 2005.
  •  928
    Most properties have comparatives, which are relations. For instance, the property of width has the comparative relation denoted by `_ is wider than _'. Let us say a property is reducible to its comparative if any statement that refers to the property has the same meaning as another statement that refers to the comparative instead. Width is not reducible to its comparative. To be sure, many statements that refer to width are reducible: for instance, `The Mississippi is wide' means the same as `T…Read more
  •  362
  •  10
    Reply to Bradley and McCarthy
    Philosophical Books 48 (4): 320-328. 2007.
  •  90
  •  5
    Representing an ordering when the population varies
    Social Choice and Welfare 20 243-6. 2003.
    This note describes a domain of distributions of wellbeing, in which different distributions may have different populations. It proves a representation theorem for an ordering defined on this domain.
  •  58
  •  55
    Précis of Rationality Through Reasoning
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 91 (1): 200-203. 2015.
  •  25
    A Reply to Sen
    Economics and Philosophy 7 (2): 285. 1991.
  •  298
    Do not ask for morality
    In Adrian Walsh, Säde Hormio & Duncan Purves (eds.), The Ethical Underpinnings of Climate Economics, Routledge. pp. 9-21. 2016.
  •  517
    Incommensurable values
    In Roger Crisp & Brad Hooker (eds.), Well-Being and Morality: Essays in Honour of James Griffin, Clarendon Press. pp. 21--38. 2000.
    Two options are incommensurate in value if neither is better than the other, and if a small improvement or worsening of one does not necessarily make it determinately better or worse than the other. If a person faces a sequence of choices between incommensurate options, she may end up with a worse options than she could have had, even though none of her choices are irrational. Yet it seems that rationality should save her from this bad outcome. This is the practical problem posed by incommensura…Read more
  •  35
    The welfare economics of population
    Social Choice and Welfare 2 221-34. 1985.
    Intuition suggests there is no value in adding people to the population if it brings no benefits to people already living: creating people is morally neutral in itself. This paper examines the difficulties of incorporating this intuition into a coherent theory of the value of population. It takes three existing theories within welfare economics - average utilitarianism, relativist utilitarianism, and critical-level utilitarianism - and considers whether they can satisfactorily accommodate the in…Read more
  •  82
    Synchronic requirements and diachronic permissions
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 45 (5-6): 630-646. 2015.
    Reasoning is an activity of ours by which we come to satisfy synchronic requirements of rationality. However, reasoning itself is regulated by diachronic permissions of rationality. For each synchronic requirement there appears to be a corresponding diachronic permission, but the requirements and permissions are not related to each other in a systematic way. It is therefore a puzzle how reasoning according to permissions can systematically bring us to satisfy requirements
  •  291
    Fairness
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91. 1991.
    John Broome; V*—Fairness, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 91, Issue 1, 1 June 1991, Pages 87–102, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/91.1.87.
  •  97
    Reply to Rabinowicz
    Philosophical Issues 19 (1): 412-417. 2009.
    No Abstract