• A Life Worth Living
    In Weighing lives, Oxford University Press. 2004.
    This chapter defines the neutral value for extending life. This is the level of a person’s temporal wellbeing at which it is just worth the person’s continuing to live: extending the life is equally as good for the person as not extending it. The chapter examines and rejects the view that extending a person’s life is normally ethically neutral. This view is analogous to the neutrality intuition about adding a person to the population. It implies that every level of wellbeing is neutral. It may b…Read more
  •  367
    A philosopher at the IPCC
    The Philosophers' Magazine 66 11-16. 2014.
  •  39
    Kamm on Fairness (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (4): 955. 1998.
  •  307
    This chapter surveys some of the issues that arise in policy making when the wellbeing of future generations must be taken into account. It analyses the discounting of future wellbeing, and considers whether it is permissible. It argues that the effects of policy on the number of future people should not be ignored, and it considers what is an appropriate basis for setting a value on these effects. It considers the implications of the non-identity effect for intergenerational justice and for the…Read more
  •  3215
    Since the last ice age, when ice enveloped most of the northern continents, the earth has warmed by about five degrees. Within a century, it is likely to warm by another four or five. This revolution in our climate will have immense and mostly harmful effects on the lives of people not yet born. We are inflicting this harm on our descendants by dumping greenhouse gases into the atmosphere. We can mitigate the harm a little by taking measures to control our emissions of these gases, and to adapt …Read more
  •  165
    The value of living longer
    In Sudhir Anand (ed.), Public Health, Ethics, and Equity, Oxford University Press Uk. pp. 243--260. 2004.
  •  142
    Practical reasoning
    In José Luis Bermúdez & Alan Millar (eds.), Reason and nature: essays in the theory of rationality, Oxford University Press. pp. 85--111. 2002.
  •  252
    Williams on Ought
    In Ulrike Heuer & Gerald R. Lang (eds.), Luck, Value, and Commitment: Themes from the Ethics of Bernard Williams, Oxford University Press Usa. 2012.
    In 2002, Bernard Williams delivered a lecture that revisited the arguments of his article 'Ought and moral obligation', published in his Moral Luck. The lecture attributed to the earlier article the thesis that there are no ‘personal’ or (as I put it) ‘owned’ oughts. It also rejected this thesis. This paper explains the idea of an owned ought, and supports Williams’s lecture in asserting that there are owned oughts. It also examines the question of how accurately Williams’s later lecture interpr…Read more
  •  90
    The unity of reasoning
    In Simon Robertson (ed.), Spheres of reason: new essays in the philosophy of normativity, Oxford University Press. 2009.
  •  256
    Should We Value Population?
    Journal of Political Philosophy 13 (4): 399-413. 2005.
  •  971
    Most properties have comparatives, which are relations. For instance, the property of width has the comparative relation denoted by `_ is wider than _'. Let us say a property is reducible to its comparative if any statement that refers to the property has the same meaning as another statement that refers to the comparative instead. Width is not reducible to its comparative. To be sure, many statements that refer to width are reducible: for instance, `The Mississippi is wide' means the same as `T…Read more
  •  367
  •  10
    Reply to Bradley and McCarthy
    Philosophical Books 48 (4): 320-328. 2007.
  •  90
  •  40
    Reply to Qizilbash
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (1). 2007.
  •  53
    Replies
    Economics and Philosophy 23 (1): 115-124. 2007.
    I am extremely grateful to the five commentators for readingmy book and offering such interesting thoughts in reaction. Shortage of space may make my responses seem brusque. But of course they are not meant to be.
  •  316
  •  117
    Dorsey rejects Conclusion, so he believes he must reject one of the premises. He argues that the best option is to reject Premise 3. Rejecting Premise 3 entails a certain sort of discontinuity in value. So Dorsey believes he has an argument for discontinuity
  •  1
  •  72
    Have we reason to do as rationality requires? - a comment on Raz
    Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 1 (Symposium): 1-10. 2005.
    No abstract
  •  40
    The mutual determination of wants and benefits
    Theory and Decision 37 (3): 333-338. 1994.
  •  5
    Some words of greeting
    Economics and Philosophy 11 (1). 1995.
  •  33
    Précis
    Philosophical Studies 173 (12): 3369-3371. 2016.
  •  555
    Wide or narrow scope?
    Mind 116 (462): 359-370. 2007.
    This paper is a response to ‘Why Be Rational?’ by Niko Kolodny. Kolodny argues that we have no reason to satisfy the requirements of rationality. His argument assumes that these requirements have a logically narrow scope. To see what the question of scope turns on, this comment provides a semantics for ‘requirement’. It shows that requirements of rationality have a wide scope, at least under one sense of ‘requirement’. Consequently Kolodny's conclusion cannot be derived.