•  18
    Modeling sustainability in economics and ecology
    In Kevin deLaplante, Bryson Brown & Kent A. Peacock (eds.), Philosophy of ecology, North-holland. pp. 11--363. 2011.
  •  1
    Sustainability
    Environmental Values 16 (2): 272-277. 2007.
  • Envircnrr. or. iii! Efrics
    Environmental Ethics: Divergence and Convergence. forthcoming.
  •  66
    A reply to my critics
    Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 20 (4): 387-405. 2007.
    Critics of my book, Sustainability, have raised many objections which are addressed. In general, I emphasize that the book is an integrative work; it must be long and complex beause it attempts a comprehensive treatment of problems of communication, of evaluation, and of management action in environmental discourse. I explain that I depend upon the pragmatists and on work in the pragmatics of language because the current language of environmental policy discourse is inadequate to allow deliberat…Read more
  •  19
    Politics and Epistemology
    Environmental Ethics 29 (3): 299-306. 2007.
    Kevin Elliott has argued that I defend two “conceptions” of adaptive management processes in my book, Sustainability: A Philosophy of Adaptive Ecosystem Management, calling the conceptions “political” and “metaphysical,” respectively. Elliott claims that I must choose between them. Elliott has not sufficiently explained how he proceeds from the claim that I provide two separable arguments for my adaptive management process to his conclusion that I have two conceptions of this process. Once this …Read more
  •  43
    Katie McShane, while accepting my 'convergence hypothesis' (the view that anthropocentrists and nonanthropocentrists will tend to propose similar policies), argues that nonanthropocentrism is nevertheless superior because it allows conservationists to have a deeper emotional commitment to natural objects than can anthropocentrists. I question this reasoning on two bases. First, McShane assumes a philosophically tendentious distinction between intrinsic and instrumental value – a distinction that…Read more
  •  88
    The past and future of environmental ethics/ philosophy
    Ethics and the Environment 12 (2): 134-136. 2007.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Past and Future of Environmental Ethics/PhilosophyBryan Norton (bio)About 15 years ago, at one of the first meetings of the group known as the International Society for Environmental Ethics (ISEE) at American Philosophical Association (APA) meetings, I drew an analogy with the field of medical ethics, arguing that environmental ethicists should look beyond philosophy departments and seek liaisons with Schools of Forestry, Schools…Read more
  •  23
    Environmental Values: An Appreciation
    Environmental Values 17 (2): 303-306. 2008.
    Review of John O'Neill, Alan Holland and Andrew Light, Environmental Values (London: Routledge, 2007 )
  •  107
    Beyond positivist ecology: Toward an integrated ecological ethics
    Science and Engineering Ethics 14 (4): 581-592. 2008.
    A post-positivist understanding of ecological science and the call for an “ecological ethic” indicate the need for a radically new approach to evaluating environmental change. The positivist view of science cannot capture the essence of environmental sciences because the recent work of “reflexive” ecological modelers shows that this requires a reconceptualization of the way in which values and ecological models interact in scientific process. Reflexive modelers are ecological modelers who believ…Read more
  •  11
    Price, Principle, and the Environment (review)
    Environmental Ethics 27 (3): 319-322. 2005.
  •  33
    Clearing the Way for a Life-Centered Ethic for Business
    The Ruffin Series of the Society for Business Ethics 2 159-165. 2000.
    I agree with much of Freeman and Reichart’s paper; so, by way of comment, I will simply supplement his argument in two ways. First, agreeing with their conclusion that we can, and should, re-direct business toward environmental protection without embracing a nonanthropocentric ethic, I will show that the pre-occupation of recent and contemporary environmental ethics with the anthropocentrism/non-anthropocentrism debate is avoidable. It rests on a misinterpretation of possible moral responses to …Read more
  •  53
    The Ways of Wickedness: Analyzing Messiness with Messy Tools (review)
    Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 25 (4): 447-465. 2012.
    The revelatory paper, “Dilemmas in the General Theory of Planning,” by Rittel and Webber (Policy Sci 4:155–169, 1973 ) has had great impact because it provides one example of an emergent consensus across many disciplines. Many “problems,” as addressed in real-world situations, involve elements that exceed the complexity of any known or hoped-for model, or are “wicked.” Many who encounter this work for the first time find that their concept of wicked problems aptly describes many environmental di…Read more
  •  26
    The convergence hypothesis asserts that, if one takes the full range of human values—present and future—into account, one will choose a set of policies that can also be accepted by an advocate of a consistent and reasonable nonanthropocentrism. Brian Steverson has attacked this hypothesis from a surprising direction. He attributes to deep ecologists the position that nonhuman nature has intrinsic value, interprets this position to mean that no species could ever be allowed to go extinct, and pro…Read more
  •  1
    Price, Principle, and the Environment (review)
    Environmental Ethics 27 (3): 319-322. 2005.