•  103
    An economic model of scientific activity and truth acquisition
    with Moshe Shaked
    Philosophical Studies 63 (1): 31-55. 1991.
    Economic forms of analysis have penetrated to many disciplines in the last 30 years: political science, sociology, law, social and political philosophy, and so forth. We wish to extend the economic paradigm to certain problems in epistemology and the philosophy of science. Scientific agents, and scholarly inquirers generally, act in some ways like vendors, trying to "sell" their findings, theories, analyses, or arguments to an audience of prospective "buyers". The analogy with the marketplace is…Read more
  •  264
    Epistemology and the evidential status of introspective reports I
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 11 (7-8): 1-16. 2004.
    The question of trusting introspective reports is a question about evidential warrant or justification. It is therefore a question of epistemology, and it behoves us to approach it within the framework of epistemology, which addresses evidential warrant across a broad spectrum of topics and sources. This paper examines the scientific status of introspective reports from the vantage point of general epistemological theorizing
  •  1132
    Philosophical intuitions: Their target, their source, and their epistemic status
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 74 (1): 1-26. 2007.
    Intuitions play a critical role in analytical philosophical activity. But do they qualify as genuine evidence for the sorts of conclusions philosophers seek? Skeptical arguments against intuitions are reviewed, and a variety of ways of trying to legitimate them are considered. A defense is offered of their evidential status by showing how their evidential status can be embedded in a naturalistic framework.
  •  337
    A Theory of Human Action
    Princeton University Press. 1970.
  •  75
    Social Routes to Belief and Knowledge
    The Monist 84 (3): 346-367. 2001.
    Many of the cognitive and social sciences deal with the question of how beliefs or belief-like states are produced and transmitted to others. Let us call any account or theory of belief-formation and propagation a doxology. I don’t use that term, of course, in the religious or theological sense. Rather, I borrow the Greek term ‘doxa’ for belief or opinion, and use ‘doxology’ to mean the study or theory of belief-forming processes. How is doxology related to epistemology? Epistemology is the theo…Read more
  • Epistemology
    In John Shand (ed.), Fundamentals of Philosophy, Routledge. pp. 11-35. 2003.
  •  384
    Why social epistemology is real epistemology
    In Duncan Pritchard, Alan Millar & Adrian Haddock (eds.), Social Epistemology, Oxford University Press. pp. 1-29. 2008.
  •  25
    Social epistemics and social psychology
    Social Epistemology 5 (2). 1991.
    J. Angelo Corlett suggests a revision in the scope of social epistemics as I have depicted it. Specifically, he suggests that social epistemics should encompass questions about certain psychological processes – viz. social cognitive processes – whereas my original proposal assigned the task of evaluating psychological processes to individual epistemics only. How compelling is this suggestion, and how consonant is it with the general program of epistemics?
  •  38
    Varieties of cognitive appraisal
    Noûs 13 (1): 23-38. 1979.
    The aim of this paper is to advance a certain non-traditional approach to epistemology. My method of introducing this approach is to compare and contrast it with more familiar epistemological orientations. Thus, the format of the paper is a survey – admittedly not exhaustive – of a variety of tasks and perspectives that epistemologists have undertaken and might undertake.
  •  8
    Innate knowledge
    In Stephen P. Stich (ed.), Innate Ideas, University of California Press. pp. 111-120. 1975.
  •  45
    Replies to the Contributors
    Philosophical Topics 29 (1-2): 461-511. 2001.
  •  232
    Cognitive Science and Metaphysics
    Journal of Philosophy 84 (10): 537-544. 1987.
    I want to explore the possible connections between cognitive science and metaphysics. Of course, on one philosophical taxonomy, metaphysics includes the philosophy of mind. So all contributions that cognitive science might make to philosophy of mind would equally be contributions to metaphysics. But I shall bracket that portion of metaphysics.
  •  346
    The individuation of action
    Journal of Philosophy 68 (21): 761-774. 1971.
  •  277
    Social epistemology is a many-splendored subject. Different theorists adopt different approaches and the options are quite diverse, often orthogonal to one another. The approach I favor is to examine social practices in terms of their impact on knowledge acquisition . This has at least two virtues: it displays continuity with traditional epistemology, which historically focuses on knowledge, and it intersects with the concerns of practical life, which are pervasively affected by what people know…Read more
  •  90
    Readings in Philosophy and Cognitive Science (edited book)
    MIT Press. 1993.
    This collection of readings shows how cognitive science can influence most of the primary branches of philosophy, as well as how philosophy critically examines the foundations of cognitive science. Its broad coverage extends beyond current texts that focus mainly on the impact of cognitive science on philosophy of mind and philosophy of psychology, to include materials that are relevant to five other branches of philosophy: epistemology, philosophy of science (and mathematics), metaphysics, lang…Read more
  •  276
    I wish to advance a certain program for doing metaphysics, a program in which cognitive science would play an important role.1 This proposed ingredient is absent from most contemporary metaphysics. There are one or two local parts of metaphysics where a role for cognitive science is commonly accepted, but I advocate a wider range of application. I begin by laying out the general program and its rationale, with selected illustrations. Then I explore in some detail a single application: the ontolo…Read more
  •  120
    Empathy, Mind, and Morals
    Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 66 (3): 17-41. 1992.
    Early Greek philosophers doubled as natural scientists; that is a common-place. It is equally true, though less often remarked, that numerous historical philosophers doubled as cognitive scientists. They constructed models of mental faculties in much the spirit of modern cognitive science, for which they are widely cited as precursors in the cognitive science literature. Today, of course, there is more emphasis on experiment, and greater division of labor. Philosophers focus on theory, foundatio…Read more
  •  49
    In the second half of the twentieth-century, the traditional problem of other minds was re-focused on special problems with propositional attitudes and how we attribute them to others. How do ordinary people, with no education in scientific psychology, understand and ascribe such complex, unobservable states? In different terminology, how do they go about "interpreting" their peers?
  •  69
    Action, causation, and unity
    Noûs 13 (2): 261-270. 1979.
    "Contingent Identity in Human Action and Philosophical Method", Castañeda's study of _A Theory of Human Action_, covers a great deal of territory and contains many diverse criticisms. In the space allotted here I cannot do justice to the range of Castañeda's detailed and careful discussion. Instead of replying to his critique point by point, let me use it as an occasion to explore a few selected topics which he broaches.
  •  1057
    For most of their respective existences, reliabilism and evidentialism (that is, process reliabilism and mentalist evidentialism) have been rivals. They are generally viewed as incompatible, even antithetical, theories of justification.1 But a few people are beginning to re-think this notion. Perhaps an ideal theory would be a hybrid of the two, combining the best elements of each theory. Juan Comesana (forthcoming) takes this point of view and constructs a position called “Evidentialist Reliabi…Read more
  • Alvin I. Goldman, Epistemology and Cognition (review)
    Synthese 79 (1): 165-169. 1989.
  •  42
    Psychology and Philosophical Analysis
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 89 (1): 195-209. 1989.
    It is often said that philosophical analysis is an a priori enterprise. Since it prominently features thought experiments designed to elicit the meaning, or semantic properties, of words in one's own language, it seems to be a purely reflective inquiry, requiring no observational or empirical component. I too have sometimes acquiesced in this sort of view. While arguing that certain phases of epistemology require input from psychology and other cognitive sciences, I have granted that the more 'c…Read more
  •  41
    Steven Lukes, Power: A Radical View (review)
    Theory and Decision 8 (3): 305-310. 1977.