•  9
    The Unity of the Epistemic Virtues
    In Pathways to Knowledge, Oxford University Press. pp. 51-72. 2002.
  •  214
    Immediate justification and process reliabilism
    In Quentin Smith (ed.), Epistemology: new essays, Oxford University Press. pp. 63-82. 2008.
  •  33
    Replies to the commentators
    Philosophia 19 (2-3): 301-324. 1989.
  •  34
    Plantinga raises two objections against reliabilism, one a putative counterexample, and the second the familiar generality problem. However, his counterexample fails when applied to a sophisticated version of reliabilism, at least the version presented in "Epistemology and Cognition". The generality problem can also be met, I believe, if cognitive process types are understood as purely psychological natural kinds, not as types that refer to external objects or circumstances, for example.
  •  50
    Functionalism, the theory-theory and phenomenology
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1): 101-108. 1993.
    The ordinary understanding and ascription of mental states is a multiply complex subject. Widely discussed approaches to the subject, such as functionalism and the theory-theory (TT), have many variations and interpretations. No surprise, then, that there are misunderstandings and disagreements, which place many items on the agenda. Unfortunately, the multiplicity of issues raised by the commentators and the limitations of space make it impossible to give a full reply to everyone. My response is…Read more
  •  415
    Reliabilism and the Value of Knowledge
    In Adrian Haddock, Alan Millar & Duncan Pritchard (eds.), Epistemic value, Oxford University Press. pp. 19-41. 2009.
  •  287
    A Moderate Approach to Embodied Cognitive Science
    Review of Philosophy and Psychology 3 (1): 71-88. 2012.
    Many current programs for cognitive science sail under the banner of “embodied cognition.” These programs typically seek to distance themselves from standard cognitive science. The present proposal for a conception of embodied cognition is less radical than most, indeed, quite compatible with many versions of traditional cognitive science. Its rationale is based on two elements, each of which is theoretically plausible and empirically well-founded. The first element invokes the idea of “bodily f…Read more
  •  310
    The Internalist Conception of Justification
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5 (1): 27-51. 1980.
    One possible aim of epistemology is to advise cognizers on the proper choice of beliefs or other doxastic attitudes. This aim has often been part of scientific methodology: to tell scientists when they should accept a given hypothesis, or give it a certain degree of credence. This regulative function is naturally linked to the notion of epistemic justification. It may well be suggested that a cognizer is justified in believing something just in case the rules of proper epistemic procedure prescr…Read more
  •  362
    Epistemic Folkways and Scientific Epistemology
    Philosophical Issues 3 271-285. 1993.
    What is the mission of epistemology, and what is its proper methodology? Such meta-epistemological questions have been prominent in recent years, especially with the emergence of various brands of "naturalistic" epistemology. In this paper, I shall reformulate and expand upon my own meta-epistemological conception (most fully articulated in Goldman, 1986), retaining many of its former ingredients while reconfiguring others. The discussion is by no means confined, though, to the meta-epistemologi…Read more
  •  325
    Précis of Knowledge in a Social World
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (1): 185-190. 1999.
    Epistemology has historically focused on individual inquirers conducting their intellectual affairs in total isolation from one another. Methodological solipsism aside, however, it is incontestable that people’s opinions are massively influenced by their community and culture, by the written and spoken words of others, both past and present. This has led recent epistemologists to pay greater attention to the social dimensions of knowledge, especially to the role of testimony as a source of justi…Read more
  •  196
    Argumentation and social epistemology
    Journal of Philosophy 91 (1): 27-49. 1994.
    What is a good argument? That depends on what is meant by 'argument'. In formal logic, an argument is a set of sentences or propositions, one designated as conclusion and the remainder as premises. On this conception of argument, there are two kinds of goodness. An argument is good in a weak sense if the conclusion either follows deductively from the premises or receives strong evidential support from them. An argument is good in a strong sense if, in addition to this, it has only true premises.…Read more
  •  121
    Speech, Truth, and the Free Market for Ideas
    with James C. Cox
    Legal Theory 2 (1): 1-32. 1996.
    This article examines a thesis of interest to social epistemology and some articulations of First Amendment legal theory: that a free market in speech is an optimal institution for promoting true belief. Under our interpretation, the market-for-speech thesis claims that more total truth possession will be achieved if speech is regulatedonlyby free market mechanisms; that is, both government regulation and private sector nonmarket regulation are held to have information-fostering properties that …Read more
  •  65
    On the measurement of power
    Journal of Philosophy 71 (8): 231-252. 1974.
    The aim of this paper is to develop a general strategy for measuring the relative power of individuals over any given issue. Three slightly different schemes will be proposed, all of which employ the same basic strategy. Although even the best of these schemes is not finally satisfactory, two important goals will be achieved: (1) the fundamental structure of the approach will be delineated, and (2) the nature of the refinement needed to obtain a fully adequate scheme will be clearly identified.
  •  285
    Social Epistemology: Theory and Applications
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 64 1-18. 2009.
    Epistemology has had a strongly individualist orientation, at least since Descartes. Knowledge, for Descartes, starts with the fact of one’s own thinking and with oneself as subject of that thinking. Whatever else can be known, it must be known by inference from one’s own mental contents. Achieving such knowledge is an individual, rather than a collective, enterprise. Descartes’s successors largely followed this lead, so the history of epistemology, down to our own time, has been a predominantly…Read more
  • Goldman's psychologism: Review of Epistemology and Cognition (review)
    Erkenntnis 34 (1): 117-123. 1986.
  •  653
    Knowledge in a social world
    Oxford University Press. 1991.
    Knowledge in a Social World offers a philosophy for the information age. Alvin Goldman explores new frontiers by creating a thoroughgoing social epistemology, moving beyond the traditional focus on solitary knowers. Against the tides of postmodernism and social constructionism Goldman defends the integrity of truth and shows how to promote it by well-designed forms of social interaction. From science to education, from law to democracy, he shows why and how public institutions should seek knowle…Read more
  •  51
    Simulation and interpersonal utility
    Ethics 105 (4): 709-726. 1995.
    The aim of this article is to show how research in cognitive science is relevant to a certain theoretical issue in moral theory, namely, the legitimacy of interpersonal utility (IU) comparisons.
  •  1524
    Discrimination and perceptual knowledge
    Journal of Philosophy 73 (November): 771-791. 1976.
    This paper presents a partial analysis of perceptual knowledge, an analysis that will, I hope, lay a foundation for a general theory of knowing. Like an earlier theory I proposed, the envisaged theory would seek to explicate the concept of knowledge by reference to the causal processes that produce (or sustain) belief. Unlike the earlier theory, however, it would abandon the requirement that a knower's belief that p be causally connected with the fact, or state of affairs, that p.
  •  79
    The real thing?
    The Philosophers' Magazine 43 88-93. 2008.
    A central group of questions are questions of an evaluative nature having to do with beliefs. What I want to say is, what we should focus on is; what are good ways of organising social practices and social institutions that are good from the point of view of what people believe, and help them get true beliefs or be informed, and then avoid making mistakes.
  •  43
    Replies to discussants
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 79 (1): 245-288. 2009.
  •  31
    Comment
    with Moshe Shaked
    Social Epistemology 7 (3). 1993.
    The paper by Susan Feigenbaum and David Levy, 'The market for (ir)reproducible econometrics', has several meritorious features. It offers an interesting model of how econometric researchers might decide whether to replicate a previously published article and how journal editors might decide whether to publish such a replication study. It offers data about error rates involved in original studies and about the willingness of original researchers to submit their data to potential replicators. Fina…Read more
  •  34
    Epistemology, two types of functionalism, and first-person authority
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2): 395-398. 1995.
    My target article did not attribute a pervasive ontological significance to phenomenology, so it escapes Bogdan's “epistemological illusion.” Pust correctly pinpoints an ambiguity between content-inclusive and content-exclusive forms of folk functionalism. Contrary to Fodor, however, only the former is plausible, and hence my third argument against functionalism remains a threat. Van Brakel's charity approach to first-person authority cannot deal with authority vis-a-vis sensations, and it has s…Read more
  •  99
    Pathways to knowledge: private and public
    Oxford University Press. 2002.
    How can we know? How can we attain justified belief? These traditional questions in epistemology have inspired philosophers for centuries. Now, in this exceptional work, Alvin Goldman, distinguished scholar and leader in the fields of epistemology and mind, approaches such inquiries as legitimate methods or "pathways" to knowledge. He examines the notion of private and public knowledge, arguing for the epistemic legitimacy of private and introspective methods of gaining knowledge, yet acknowledg…Read more
  •  103
    An economic model of scientific activity and truth acquisition
    with Moshe Shaked
    Philosophical Studies 63 (1): 31-55. 1991.
    Economic forms of analysis have penetrated to many disciplines in the last 30 years: political science, sociology, law, social and political philosophy, and so forth. We wish to extend the economic paradigm to certain problems in epistemology and the philosophy of science. Scientific agents, and scholarly inquirers generally, act in some ways like vendors, trying to "sell" their findings, theories, analyses, or arguments to an audience of prospective "buyers". The analogy with the marketplace is…Read more
  •  40
    The Cognitive and Social Sides of Epistemology
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1986 295-311. 1986.
    Epistemology should accommodate both psychological and social dimensions of knowledge. My framework, called 'epistemics,' divides into individual and social epistemics. Primary individual epistemics, which is closely allied with cognitive science, studies the epistemic properties of basic cognitive operations. Examples are given, focusing on belief perseverance, imagery, deductive reasoning, and acceptance (as modeled by the "connectionist" approach). Social epistemics targets such things as com…Read more
  •  263
    Epistemology and the evidential status of introspective reports I
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 11 (7-8): 1-16. 2004.
    The question of trusting introspective reports is a question about evidential warrant or justification. It is therefore a question of epistemology, and it behoves us to approach it within the framework of epistemology, which addresses evidential warrant across a broad spectrum of topics and sources. This paper examines the scientific status of introspective reports from the vantage point of general epistemological theorizing
  •  1129
    Philosophical intuitions: Their target, their source, and their epistemic status
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 74 (1): 1-26. 2007.
    Intuitions play a critical role in analytical philosophical activity. But do they qualify as genuine evidence for the sorts of conclusions philosophers seek? Skeptical arguments against intuitions are reviewed, and a variety of ways of trying to legitimate them are considered. A defense is offered of their evidential status by showing how their evidential status can be embedded in a naturalistic framework.
  •  335
    A Theory of Human Action
    Princeton University Press. 1970.