•  51
    This collection of essays by Alvin Goldman explores an array of topics in the philosophy of cognitive science, ranging from embodied cognition to the metaphysics of actions and events.
  •  59
    Reply to commentators (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (1). 2002.
    I am most appreciative of the careful and incisive commentaries on KSW that Professors Kitcher, Talbott, and Copp have produced. They have pressed me to think more deeply about a number of issues of importance to social epistemology. Since their commentaries focus on completely different topics, I shall reply to them independently.
  •  54
    Christopher Peacocke, Being known (review)
    Mind 110 (440): 1105-1109. 2001.
  •  170
    The relation between epistemology and psychology
    Synthese 64 (1): 29-68. 1985.
    In the wake of Frege's attack on psychologism and the subsequent influence of Logical Positivism, psychological considerations in philosophy came to be viewed with suspicion. Philosophical questions, especially epistemological ones, were viewed as 'logical' questions, and logic was sharply separated from psychology. Various efforts have been made of late to reconnect epistemology with psychology. But there is little agreement about how such connections should be made, and doubts about the place …Read more
  •  6
    This chapter considers how imagination generates emotion. ‘Supposition-imagination’ (S-imagination) is distinguished from ‘enactment-imagination’ (E-imagination). The former kind of imagination involves entertaining or supposing various hypothetical scenarios; with the latter kind of imagination, one tries to create a kind of facsimile of a mental state. Thus, one might try to create a perception-like state as in visual imagination or motoric imagination. It is argued that this much richer form …Read more
  •  34
    Power, time, and cost
    Philosophical Studies 26 (3-4): 263-270. 1974.
    David Braybrooke makes two criticisms of my theory of social power, one that deals with the time of power and one that concerns the relation between power and cost. In his first criticism he points out that, according to my analysis, Richard Nixon had the power, in 1940, to nominate Burger for Chief Justice in 1970, and a certain twelve-year old boy may today have the power to hit the first home run of the 1990 season. Braybrooke finds these consequences of the theory unacceptable. These agents …Read more
  •  79
    An Epistemological Approach to Argumentation
    Informal Logic 23 (1): 51-63. 2003.
    The evaluation of arguments and argumentation is best understood epistemologically. Epistemic circularity is not formally defective but it may be epistemologically objectionable. Sorenson's doubts about the syntactic approach to circularity are endorsed with qualifications. One explanation of an argument's goodness is its ability to produce justified belief in its conclusion by means of justified belief in its premises, but matters are not so simple for interpersonal argumentation. Even when an …Read more
  •  421
    Epistemics: The regulative theory of cognition
    Journal of Philosophy 75 (10): 509-523. 1978.
    I wish to advocate a reorientation of epistemology. Lest anyone maintain that the enterprise I urge is not epistemology at all (even part of epistemology), I call this enterprise by a slightly different name: epistemics. Despite this terminological concession, I believe that the inquiry I advocate is significantly continuous with traditional epistemology. Like much of past epistemology, it would seek to regulate or guide our intellectual activities. It would try to lay down principles or suggest…Read more
  •  216
    Naturalistic Epistemology and Reliabilism
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 19 (1): 301-320. 1994.
  •  51
    Stephen P. Stich: The Fragmentation of Reason
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (1): 189-193. 1991.
  •  23
    Episteme: A new self-definition
    Episteme 9 (1): 1-2. 2012.
    With this issue Episteme makes its debut with Cambridge University Press, after eight successful years of publication at Edinburgh University Press. The journal’s new subtitle reflects a significant expansion in scope and mission. Our previous subtitle, ‘A Journal of Social Epistemology’, reflected our earlier focus on the nascent field of social epistemology. The new subtitle, ‘A Journal of Individual and Social Epistemology’, reflects a new self-definition as a full-spectrum journal of epistem…Read more
  •  55
    Robert Nozick, Philosophical Explanations (review)
    Philosophical Review 92 (1): 81-88. 1983.
  •  10
    Social Epistemology
    Critica 31 (93): 3-19. 1999.
    Epistemology has historically focused on individual inquirers conducting their private intellectual affairs independently of one another. As a descriptive matter, however, what people believe and know is largely a function of their community and culture, narrowly or broadly construed. Most of what we believe is influenced, directly or indirectly, by the utterances and writings of others. So social epistemology deserves at least equal standing alongside the individual sector of epistemology.
  •  33
    Does one size fit all? Hurley on shared circuits
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (1): 27-28. 2008.
    Hurley's high level of generality suggests that a control-theoretic framework underpins all of the phenomena in question, but this is problematic. In contrast to the action-perception domain, where the control-theoretic framework certainly applies, there is no evidence that this framework equally applies to feelings and emotions, such as pain, touch, and disgust, where mirroring and simulational mindreading are also found
  •  213
    Williamson on Knowledge and Evidence
    In Patrick Greenough & Duncan Pritchard (eds.), Williamson on Knowledge, Oxford University Press. pp. 73-91. 2009.
  •  59
    Mindreading by simulation: The roles of imagination and mirroring
    with Lucy C. Jordan
    In Simon Baron-Cohen, Michael Lombardo & Helen Tager-Flusberg (eds.), Understanding Other Minds: Perspectives From Developmental Social Neuroscience (3rd ed.), Oxford University Press. pp. 448-466. 2013.
  •  33
    Replies to the commentators
    Philosophia 19 (2-3): 301-324. 1989.
  •  34
    Plantinga raises two objections against reliabilism, one a putative counterexample, and the second the familiar generality problem. However, his counterexample fails when applied to a sophisticated version of reliabilism, at least the version presented in "Epistemology and Cognition". The generality problem can also be met, I believe, if cognitive process types are understood as purely psychological natural kinds, not as types that refer to external objects or circumstances, for example.
  •  9
    The Unity of the Epistemic Virtues
    In Pathways to Knowledge, Oxford University Press. pp. 51-72. 2002.
  •  214
    Immediate justification and process reliabilism
    In Quentin Smith (ed.), Epistemology: new essays, Oxford University Press. pp. 63-82. 2008.
  •  415
    Reliabilism and the Value of Knowledge
    In Adrian Haddock, Alan Millar & Duncan Pritchard (eds.), Epistemic value, Oxford University Press. pp. 19-41. 2009.
  •  287
    A Moderate Approach to Embodied Cognitive Science
    Review of Philosophy and Psychology 3 (1): 71-88. 2012.
    Many current programs for cognitive science sail under the banner of “embodied cognition.” These programs typically seek to distance themselves from standard cognitive science. The present proposal for a conception of embodied cognition is less radical than most, indeed, quite compatible with many versions of traditional cognitive science. Its rationale is based on two elements, each of which is theoretically plausible and empirically well-founded. The first element invokes the idea of “bodily f…Read more
  •  310
    The Internalist Conception of Justification
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5 (1): 27-51. 1980.
    One possible aim of epistemology is to advise cognizers on the proper choice of beliefs or other doxastic attitudes. This aim has often been part of scientific methodology: to tell scientists when they should accept a given hypothesis, or give it a certain degree of credence. This regulative function is naturally linked to the notion of epistemic justification. It may well be suggested that a cognizer is justified in believing something just in case the rules of proper epistemic procedure prescr…Read more
  •  50
    Functionalism, the theory-theory and phenomenology
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1): 101-108. 1993.
    The ordinary understanding and ascription of mental states is a multiply complex subject. Widely discussed approaches to the subject, such as functionalism and the theory-theory (TT), have many variations and interpretations. No surprise, then, that there are misunderstandings and disagreements, which place many items on the agenda. Unfortunately, the multiplicity of issues raised by the commentators and the limitations of space make it impossible to give a full reply to everyone. My response is…Read more
  •  325
    Précis of Knowledge in a Social World
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (1): 185-190. 1999.
    Epistemology has historically focused on individual inquirers conducting their intellectual affairs in total isolation from one another. Methodological solipsism aside, however, it is incontestable that people’s opinions are massively influenced by their community and culture, by the written and spoken words of others, both past and present. This has led recent epistemologists to pay greater attention to the social dimensions of knowledge, especially to the role of testimony as a source of justi…Read more
  •  196
    Argumentation and social epistemology
    Journal of Philosophy 91 (1): 27-49. 1994.
    What is a good argument? That depends on what is meant by 'argument'. In formal logic, an argument is a set of sentences or propositions, one designated as conclusion and the remainder as premises. On this conception of argument, there are two kinds of goodness. An argument is good in a weak sense if the conclusion either follows deductively from the premises or receives strong evidential support from them. An argument is good in a strong sense if, in addition to this, it has only true premises.…Read more
  •  121
    Speech, Truth, and the Free Market for Ideas
    with James C. Cox
    Legal Theory 2 (1): 1-32. 1996.
    This article examines a thesis of interest to social epistemology and some articulations of First Amendment legal theory: that a free market in speech is an optimal institution for promoting true belief. Under our interpretation, the market-for-speech thesis claims that more total truth possession will be achieved if speech is regulatedonlyby free market mechanisms; that is, both government regulation and private sector nonmarket regulation are held to have information-fostering properties that …Read more
  •  362
    Epistemic Folkways and Scientific Epistemology
    Philosophical Issues 3 271-285. 1993.
    What is the mission of epistemology, and what is its proper methodology? Such meta-epistemological questions have been prominent in recent years, especially with the emergence of various brands of "naturalistic" epistemology. In this paper, I shall reformulate and expand upon my own meta-epistemological conception (most fully articulated in Goldman, 1986), retaining many of its former ingredients while reconfiguring others. The discussion is by no means confined, though, to the meta-epistemologi…Read more
  •  285
    Social Epistemology: Theory and Applications
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 64 1-18. 2009.
    Epistemology has had a strongly individualist orientation, at least since Descartes. Knowledge, for Descartes, starts with the fact of one’s own thinking and with oneself as subject of that thinking. Whatever else can be known, it must be known by inference from one’s own mental contents. Achieving such knowledge is an individual, rather than a collective, enterprise. Descartes’s successors largely followed this lead, so the history of epistemology, down to our own time, has been a predominantly…Read more