•  65
    Derived intentionality?
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3): 514. 1988.
  •  65
    On the measurement of power
    Journal of Philosophy 71 (8): 231-252. 1974.
    The aim of this paper is to develop a general strategy for measuring the relative power of individuals over any given issue. Three slightly different schemes will be proposed, all of which employ the same basic strategy. Although even the best of these schemes is not finally satisfactory, two important goals will be achieved: (1) the fundamental structure of the approach will be delineated, and (2) the nature of the refinement needed to obtain a fully adequate scheme will be clearly identified.
  •  62
    Commentary on Jack Lyons’s Perception and Basic Beliefs
    Philosophical Studies 153 (3): 457-466. 2011.
    This book deserves kudos. It presents one of the more novel versions of reliabilism to appear in recent years. The style is fast-paced and energetic, with no sacrifice in philosophical precision. It applies original interpretations of perceptual science to central issues in traditional epistemology, and should thereby earn itself a prominent place in the naturalistic epistemology literature. Finally, the book is more comprehensive than its title suggests. It illuminates a great many issues of tr…Read more
  •  61
  •  59
    Reply to commentators (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (1). 2002.
    I am most appreciative of the careful and incisive commentaries on KSW that Professors Kitcher, Talbott, and Copp have produced. They have pressed me to think more deeply about a number of issues of importance to social epistemology. Since their commentaries focus on completely different topics, I shall reply to them independently.
  •  59
    Mindreading by simulation: The roles of imagination and mirroring
    with Lucy C. Jordan
    In Simon Baron-Cohen, Michael Lombardo & Helen Tager-Flusberg (eds.), Understanding Other Minds: Perspectives From Developmental Social Neuroscience (3rd ed.), Oxford University Press. pp. 448-466. 2013.
  •  57
    Psychological, Social, and Epistemic Factors in the Theory of Science
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1994 277-286. 1994.
    This article blends psychological and social factors in the explanation of science, and defends the compatibility of a psychosocial picture with an epistemic picture. It examines three variants of the 'political' approach to interpersonal persuasion advocated by Latour and others. In each case an 'epistemic' or mixed account is more promising and empirically better supported. Psychological research on motivated reasoning shows the epistemic limits of interest-driven belief. Against social constr…Read more
  •  55
    Robert Nozick, Philosophical Explanations (review)
    Philosophical Review 92 (1): 81-88. 1983.
  •  54
    Christopher Peacocke, Being known (review)
    Mind 110 (440): 1105-1109. 2001.
  •  51
    This collection of essays by Alvin Goldman explores an array of topics in the philosophy of cognitive science, ranging from embodied cognition to the metaphysics of actions and events.
  •  51
    Stephen P. Stich: The Fragmentation of Reason
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (1): 189-193. 1991.
  •  51
    Simulation and interpersonal utility
    Ethics 105 (4): 709-726. 1995.
    The aim of this article is to show how research in cognitive science is relevant to a certain theoretical issue in moral theory, namely, the legitimacy of interpersonal utility (IU) comparisons.
  •  50
    Metaphysics and Cognitive Science (edited book)
    with Brian P. McLaughlin
    Oxford University Press. 2019.
    This volume illustrates how the methodology of metaphysics can be enriched with the help of cognitive science. Few philosophers nowadays would dispute the relevance of cognitive science to the metaphysics of mind, but this volume mainly concerns the relevance of metaphysics to phenomena that are not themselves mental. The volume is thus a departure from standard analytical metaphysics. Among the issues to which results from cognitive science are brought to bear are the metaphysics of time, of mo…Read more
  •  50
    Functionalism, the theory-theory and phenomenology
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1): 101-108. 1993.
    The ordinary understanding and ascription of mental states is a multiply complex subject. Widely discussed approaches to the subject, such as functionalism and the theory-theory (TT), have many variations and interpretations. No surprise, then, that there are misunderstandings and disagreements, which place many items on the agenda. Unfortunately, the multiplicity of issues raised by the commentators and the limitations of space make it impossible to give a full reply to everyone. My response is…Read more
  •  49
    In the second half of the twentieth-century, the traditional problem of other minds was re-focused on special problems with propositional attitudes and how we attribute them to others. How do ordinary people, with no education in scientific psychology, understand and ascribe such complex, unobservable states? In different terminology, how do they go about "interpreting" their peers?
  •  49
    Replies to reviews of Knowledge in a Social World
    Social Epistemology 14 (4): 317-333. 2000.
    The order I shall discuss these reviews is roughly the order of the chapters on which they centre. Some commentaries, of course, address material from more than one chapter, but I usually take either the first or the principal chapter they write about as my guide.
  •  48
    Ziff on the Inconsistency of English
    Analysis 22 (5): 106. 1962.
    In an _obiter dictum_ of his recent book _Semantic Analysis_, Paul Ziff discusses the claim that the existence of so-called 'semantic paradoxes' establishes the inconsistency of the English language. Ziff argues that this claim is not justified. I shall try to show that, whether or not the claim is justified, Ziff's argument against it is not a good one.
  •  45
    Replies to the Contributors
    Philosophical Topics 29 (1-2): 461-511. 2001.
  •  43
    Replies to discussants
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 79 (1): 245-288. 2009.
  •  42
    Psychology and Philosophical Analysis
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 89 (1): 195-209. 1989.
    It is often said that philosophical analysis is an a priori enterprise. Since it prominently features thought experiments designed to elicit the meaning, or semantic properties, of words in one's own language, it seems to be a purely reflective inquiry, requiring no observational or empirical component. I too have sometimes acquiesced in this sort of view. While arguing that certain phases of epistemology require input from psychology and other cognitive sciences, I have granted that the more 'c…Read more
  •  41
    Steven Lukes, Power: A Radical View (review)
    Theory and Decision 8 (3): 305-310. 1977.
  •  41
    Consciousness researchers standardly rely on their subjects’ verbal reports to ascertain which conscious states they are in. What justifies this reliance on verbal reports? Does it comport with the third-person approach characteristic of science, or does it ultimately appeal to first-person knowledge of consciousness? If first-person knowledge is required, does this pass scientific muster? Several attempts to rationalize the reliance on verbal reports are considered, beginning with attempts to d…Read more
  •  40
    The Cognitive and Social Sides of Epistemology
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1986 295-311. 1986.
    Epistemology should accommodate both psychological and social dimensions of knowledge. My framework, called 'epistemics,' divides into individual and social epistemics. Primary individual epistemics, which is closely allied with cognitive science, studies the epistemic properties of basic cognitive operations. Examples are given, focusing on belief perseverance, imagery, deductive reasoning, and acceptance (as modeled by the "connectionist" approach). Social epistemics targets such things as com…Read more
  •  38
    Varieties of cognitive appraisal
    Noûs 13 (1): 23-38. 1979.
    The aim of this paper is to advance a certain non-traditional approach to epistemology. My method of introducing this approach is to compare and contrast it with more familiar epistemological orientations. Thus, the format of the paper is a survey – admittedly not exhaustive – of a variety of tasks and perspectives that epistemologists have undertaken and might undertake.
  •  37
    Legal evidence
    In Martin P. Golding & William A. Edmundson (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory, Blackwell. pp. 163-175. 2004.
    This chapter contains section titled: Scope of the Topic A Unified Theory: The Search for Truth The Adversary System and the Search for Truth Truth, Reliability, and Bayesianism Applications of Quasi‐objective Bayesianism References Further Reading.
  •  34
    Power, time, and cost
    Philosophical Studies 26 (3-4): 263-270. 1974.
    David Braybrooke makes two criticisms of my theory of social power, one that deals with the time of power and one that concerns the relation between power and cost. In his first criticism he points out that, according to my analysis, Richard Nixon had the power, in 1940, to nominate Burger for Chief Justice in 1970, and a certain twelve-year old boy may today have the power to hit the first home run of the 1990 season. Braybrooke finds these consequences of the theory unacceptable. These agents …Read more
  •  34
    Plantinga raises two objections against reliabilism, one a putative counterexample, and the second the familiar generality problem. However, his counterexample fails when applied to a sophisticated version of reliabilism, at least the version presented in "Epistemology and Cognition". The generality problem can also be met, I believe, if cognitive process types are understood as purely psychological natural kinds, not as types that refer to external objects or circumstances, for example.