•  369
    Mirroring, simulating and mindreading
    Mind and Language 24 (2): 235-252. 2009.
    Pierre Jacob (2008) raises several problems for the alleged link between mirroring and mindreading. This response argues that the best mirroring-mindreading thesis would claim that mirror processes cause, rather than constitute, selected acts of mindreading. Second, the best current evidence for mirror-based mindreading is not found in the motoric domain but in the domains of emotion and sensation, where the evidence (ignored by Jacob) is substantial. Finally, simulation theory should distinguis…Read more
  •  273
    Social epistemology is the normative theory of socioepistemic practices. Teaching is a socioepistemic practice, so educational practices belong on the agenda of social epistemology. A current question is whether intelligent design should be taught in biology classes. This paper focuses on the argument from “fairness” or “equal time.” The principal aim of education is knowledge transmission, but evidence renders it doubtful that giving intelligent design equal time would promote knowledge transmi…Read more
  •  119
    Ethics and cognitive science
    Ethics 103 (2): 337-360. 1993.
    Findings and theories in cognitive science have been increasingly important in many areas of philosophy, especially philosophy of mind, epistemology, and philosophy of language. The time is ripe to examine its potential applications to moral theory as well. This article does not aspire to a comprehensive treatment of the subject. It merely aims to illustrate the ways in which research in cognitive science can bear on the concerns of moral philosophers. For present purposes the label 'cognitive s…Read more
  •  51
    This collection of essays by Alvin Goldman explores an array of topics in the philosophy of cognitive science, ranging from embodied cognition to the metaphysics of actions and events.
  •  274
    Reliabilism, veritism, and epistemic consequentialism
    Episteme 12 (2): 131-143. 2015.
    According to Selim Berker the prevalence of consequentialism in contemporary epistemology rivals its prevalence in contemporary ethics. Similarly, and more to the point, Berker finds epistemic consequentialism, epitomized by process reliabilism, to be as misguided and problematic as ethical consequentialism. This paper shows how Berker misconstrues process reliabilism and fails to pinpoint any new or substantial defects in it.
  •  89
    Chisholm's theory of action
    Philosophia 7 (3-4): 583-596. 1978.
    In any generation there are relatively few people who make major original contributions to even a single area of philosophy. But the man whose work is the topic of this conference has made such contributions not only in a single field, but in several. This morning and afternoon we have devoted our attention to Chisholm's epistemology, the breadth and significance of which is evident. Equally deserving of our attention, however, are his contributions to the theory of action and metaphysics, and w…Read more
  •  356
    Why Citizens Should Vote: A Causal Responsibility Approach
    Social Philosophy and Policy 16 (2): 201-217. 1999.
    Why should a citizen vote? There are two ways to interpret this question: in a prudential sense, and in a moral sense. Under the first interpretation, the question asks why—or under what circumstances—it is in a citizen's self-interest to vote. Under the second interpretation, it asks what moral reasons citizens have for voting. I shall mainly try to answer the moral version of the question, but my answer may also, in some circumstances, bear on the prudential question. Before proceeding to my o…Read more
  •  6
    This chapter considers how imagination generates emotion. ‘Supposition-imagination’ (S-imagination) is distinguished from ‘enactment-imagination’ (E-imagination). The former kind of imagination involves entertaining or supposing various hypothetical scenarios; with the latter kind of imagination, one tries to create a kind of facsimile of a mental state. Thus, one might try to create a perception-like state as in visual imagination or motoric imagination. It is argued that this much richer form …Read more
  •  59
    Reply to commentators (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (1). 2002.
    I am most appreciative of the careful and incisive commentaries on KSW that Professors Kitcher, Talbott, and Copp have produced. They have pressed me to think more deeply about a number of issues of importance to social epistemology. Since their commentaries focus on completely different topics, I shall reply to them independently.
  •  54
    Christopher Peacocke, Being known (review)
    Mind 110 (440): 1105-1109. 2001.
  •  170
    The relation between epistemology and psychology
    Synthese 64 (1): 29-68. 1985.
    In the wake of Frege's attack on psychologism and the subsequent influence of Logical Positivism, psychological considerations in philosophy came to be viewed with suspicion. Philosophical questions, especially epistemological ones, were viewed as 'logical' questions, and logic was sharply separated from psychology. Various efforts have been made of late to reconnect epistemology with psychology. But there is little agreement about how such connections should be made, and doubts about the place …Read more
  •  34
    Power, time, and cost
    Philosophical Studies 26 (3-4): 263-270. 1974.
    David Braybrooke makes two criticisms of my theory of social power, one that deals with the time of power and one that concerns the relation between power and cost. In his first criticism he points out that, according to my analysis, Richard Nixon had the power, in 1940, to nominate Burger for Chief Justice in 1970, and a certain twelve-year old boy may today have the power to hit the first home run of the 1990 season. Braybrooke finds these consequences of the theory unacceptable. These agents …Read more
  •  79
    An Epistemological Approach to Argumentation
    Informal Logic 23 (1): 51-63. 2003.
    The evaluation of arguments and argumentation is best understood epistemologically. Epistemic circularity is not formally defective but it may be epistemologically objectionable. Sorenson's doubts about the syntactic approach to circularity are endorsed with qualifications. One explanation of an argument's goodness is its ability to produce justified belief in its conclusion by means of justified belief in its premises, but matters are not so simple for interpersonal argumentation. Even when an …Read more
  •  421
    Epistemics: The regulative theory of cognition
    Journal of Philosophy 75 (10): 509-523. 1978.
    I wish to advocate a reorientation of epistemology. Lest anyone maintain that the enterprise I urge is not epistemology at all (even part of epistemology), I call this enterprise by a slightly different name: epistemics. Despite this terminological concession, I believe that the inquiry I advocate is significantly continuous with traditional epistemology. Like much of past epistemology, it would seek to regulate or guide our intellectual activities. It would try to lay down principles or suggest…Read more
  •  55
    Robert Nozick, Philosophical Explanations (review)
    Philosophical Review 92 (1): 81-88. 1983.
  •  216
    Naturalistic Epistemology and Reliabilism
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 19 (1): 301-320. 1994.
  •  51
    Stephen P. Stich: The Fragmentation of Reason
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (1): 189-193. 1991.
  •  23
    Episteme: A new self-definition
    Episteme 9 (1): 1-2. 2012.
    With this issue Episteme makes its debut with Cambridge University Press, after eight successful years of publication at Edinburgh University Press. The journal’s new subtitle reflects a significant expansion in scope and mission. Our previous subtitle, ‘A Journal of Social Epistemology’, reflected our earlier focus on the nascent field of social epistemology. The new subtitle, ‘A Journal of Individual and Social Epistemology’, reflects a new self-definition as a full-spectrum journal of epistem…Read more
  •  59
    Mindreading by simulation: The roles of imagination and mirroring
    with Lucy C. Jordan
    In Simon Baron-Cohen, Michael Lombardo & Helen Tager-Flusberg (eds.), Understanding Other Minds: Perspectives From Developmental Social Neuroscience (3rd ed.), Oxford University Press. pp. 448-466. 2013.
  •  10
    Social Epistemology
    Critica 31 (93): 3-19. 1999.
    Epistemology has historically focused on individual inquirers conducting their private intellectual affairs independently of one another. As a descriptive matter, however, what people believe and know is largely a function of their community and culture, narrowly or broadly construed. Most of what we believe is influenced, directly or indirectly, by the utterances and writings of others. So social epistemology deserves at least equal standing alongside the individual sector of epistemology.
  •  33
    Does one size fit all? Hurley on shared circuits
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (1): 27-28. 2008.
    Hurley's high level of generality suggests that a control-theoretic framework underpins all of the phenomena in question, but this is problematic. In contrast to the action-perception domain, where the control-theoretic framework certainly applies, there is no evidence that this framework equally applies to feelings and emotions, such as pain, touch, and disgust, where mirroring and simulational mindreading are also found
  •  213
    Williamson on Knowledge and Evidence
    In Patrick Greenough & Duncan Pritchard (eds.), Williamson on Knowledge, Oxford University Press. pp. 73-91. 2009.
  •  214
    Immediate justification and process reliabilism
    In Quentin Smith (ed.), Epistemology: new essays, Oxford University Press. pp. 63-82. 2008.
  •  33
    Replies to the commentators
    Philosophia 19 (2-3): 301-324. 1989.
  •  34
    Plantinga raises two objections against reliabilism, one a putative counterexample, and the second the familiar generality problem. However, his counterexample fails when applied to a sophisticated version of reliabilism, at least the version presented in "Epistemology and Cognition". The generality problem can also be met, I believe, if cognitive process types are understood as purely psychological natural kinds, not as types that refer to external objects or circumstances, for example.
  •  9
    The Unity of the Epistemic Virtues
    In Pathways to Knowledge, Oxford University Press. pp. 51-72. 2002.
  •  415
    Reliabilism and the Value of Knowledge
    In Adrian Haddock, Alan Millar & Duncan Pritchard (eds.), Epistemic value, Oxford University Press. pp. 19-41. 2009.
  •  287
    A Moderate Approach to Embodied Cognitive Science
    Review of Philosophy and Psychology 3 (1): 71-88. 2012.
    Many current programs for cognitive science sail under the banner of “embodied cognition.” These programs typically seek to distance themselves from standard cognitive science. The present proposal for a conception of embodied cognition is less radical than most, indeed, quite compatible with many versions of traditional cognitive science. Its rationale is based on two elements, each of which is theoretically plausible and empirically well-founded. The first element invokes the idea of “bodily f…Read more