•  38
    Pyrrhonian Reflections on Knowledge and Justification (review)
    International Philosophical Quarterly 37 (1): 115-119. 1997.
  •  147
    Virtue, Luck and the Pyrrhonian Problematic
    Philosophical Studies 130 (1): 9-34. 2006.
    A number of contemporary philosophers endorse a Pyrrhonian theme: that one has knowledge only if one knows or understands that one’s beliefs are reliably formed. Otherwise, one is like a man who grasps gold in the dark: such a man is successful, but his success is a matter of luck, and so not creditable to him. It is argued that the skeptical problem and the problem of moral luck share a common structure and a common solution. Specifically, a virtue-theoretic approach helps us to understand impo…Read more
  •  26
    A Realist Conception of Truth (review)
    International Philosophical Quarterly 38 (3): 313-317. 1998.
  •  3249
    Knowledge as Credit for True Belief
    In Michael DePaul & Linda Zagzebski (eds.), Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives From Ethics and Epistemology, Clarendon Press. pp. 111-134. 2003.
    The paper begins by reviewing two problems for fallibilism: the lottery problem, or the problem of explaining why fallible evidence, though otherwise excellent, is not enough to know that one will lose the lottery, and Gettier problems. It is then argued that both problems can be resolved if we note an important illocutionary force of knowledge attributions: namely, that when we attribute knowledge to someone we mean to give the person credit for getting things right. Alternatively, to say that …Read more
  •  225
    Virtues and Vices of Virtue Epistemology
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 23 (3): 413-432. 1993.
    In recent years, virtue epistemology has won the attention of a wide range of philosophers. A developed form of the position has been expounded forcefully by Ernest Sosa and represents the most plausible version of reliabilism to date. Through the person of Alvin Plantinga, virtue epistemology has taken philosophy of religion by storm, evoking objections and defenses in a wide variety of journals and volumes. Historically, virtue epistemology has its roots in the work of Thomas Reid, and the exp…Read more
  •  165
    Cognitive integration and the ownership of belief: Response to Bernecker
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (1). 2008.
    This paper responds to Sven Bernecker’s argument that agent reliabilism cannot accommodate internalist intuitions about clarvoyance cases. In section 1 we clarify a version of agent reliabilism and Bernecker’s objections against it. In section 2 we say more about how the notion of cognitive integration helps to adjudicate clairvoyance cases and other proposed counterexamples to reliabilism. The central idea is that cognitive integration underwrites a kind of belief ownership, which in turn und…Read more
  •  1
    The Blackwell Guide to Epistemology
    Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 64 (2): 405-405. 2002.
  •  3
    Epistemic Value
    Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2009.
  •  22
    Skepticism and the Modern Ontology
    Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 73 217-228. 1999.
  •  84
    In this paper I offer a solution to scepticism about the world which neither embraces idealism, nor ends in a stalemate, nor begs the question against the sceptic. In the first part of the paper I explicate the sceptical argument and try to show why it has real force. In the next part of the paper I propose a version of the relevant possibilities approach to scepticism. The central claim of the proposed solution is that a sceptical possibility undermines knowledge only if the possibility is true…Read more
  •  29
    Evidence and Inquiry (review)
    International Philosophical Quarterly 36 (2): 231-234. 1996.
  •  161
    Religious Knowledge in the Context of Conflicting Testimony
    Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 83 61-76. 2009.
    An adequate account of testimonial knowledge in general explains how religious knowledge can be grounded in testimony, and even in the context of conflicting testimonial traditions. Three emerging trends in epistemology help to make that case. The first is to make a distinction between two projects of epistemology: “the project of explanation” and “the project of vindication.” The second is to emphasize a distinction between knowledge and understanding. The third is to ask what role the concept …Read more
  •  414
    What is transmission*?
    Episteme 13 (4): 481-498. 2016.
    Almost everyone believes that testimony can transmit knowledge from speaker to hearer. What some philosophers mean by this is ordinary and pedestrian-- they mean only that, in at least some cases, a speaker S knows that p, S testifies that p to a hearer H, and H comes to know that p as a result of believing S's testimony. There is disagreement about how this occurs, but that it does occur is sufficient for the transmission of knowledge in the intended sense. On this understanding of transmissi…Read more
  •  83
    Cognitive Integration and the Ownership of Belief: Response to Bernecker
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (1): 173-184. 2008.
    Sven Bernecker has raised questions about how agent reliabilism should adjudicate clairvoyance cases.1 Bernecker’s charge is that the view cannot accommodate internalist intuitions about such cases while remaining psychologically plausible. His more specific charge is that invoking the notion of cognitive integration does not help. This paper responds to Bernecker’s charges. In section 1 we clarify a version of agent reliabilism and Bernecker’s objections against it. In section 2 we say more abo…Read more
  •  80
    Plantinga, Foundationalism, and the Charge of Self-referential Incoherence
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 31 (1): 187-193. 1988.
    Alvin Plantinga charges classical foundationalism with self-referential incoherence, meaning that that doctrine employs criteria for rationally acceptable propositions which exclude the criteria themselves. More specifically, the charge is that the criteria are neither properly basic nor supported by properly basic propositions. In section 1 the doctrine of classical foundationalism is briefly explained. In section 2, a defense against Plantinga's objection is provided showing how the foundation…Read more
  •  149
    Virtue Epistemology: Contemporary Readings (edited book)
    with John Turri
    MIT Press. 2012.
    Virtue epistemology is a diverse and flourishing field, one of the most exciting developments in epistemology to emerge over the last three decades. Virtue epistemology begins with the premise that epistemology is a normative discipline and, accordingly, a central task of epistemology is to explain the sort of normativity that knowledge, justified belief, and the like involve. A second premise is that a focus on the intellectual virtues is essential to carrying out this central task. This collec…Read more
  •  309
    Agent reliabilism
    Philosophical Perspectives 13 273-296. 1999.
    This paper reviews two skeptical arguments and argues that a reliabilist framework is necessary to avoid them. The paper also argues that agent reliabilism, which makes the knower the seat of reliability, is the most plausible version of reliabilism.
  •  249
    How to Reid Moore
    Philosophical Quarterly 52 (209): 544-563. 2002.
    Moore's 'Proof of an External World' has evoked a variety of responses from philosophers, including bafflement, indignation and sympathetic reconstruction. I argue that Moore should be understood as following Thomas Reid on a variety of points, both epistemological and methodological. Moreover, Moore and Reid are exactly right on all of these points. Hence what I present is a defence of Moore's 'Proof', as well as an interpretation. Finally, I argue that the Reid-Moore position is useful for…Read more
  •  15
    The Nature of Ability and the Purpose of Knowledge
    Philosophical Issues 17 (1): 57-69. 2007.
  •  8
    Speaking of a Personal God (review)
    Faith and Philosophy 12 (1): 148-153. 1995.
  •  34
    John Greco’s Putting Skeptics in Their Place is an important book. Greco persuasively argues that the best skeptical arguments cannot be easily dismissed and should not be ignored. These arguments cannot be easily dismissed because they defend important conclusions and make no obvious mistake. The arguments should not be ignored because their proper analysis reveals much about central philosophical notions such as knowledge and evidence. While defending these conclusions Greco offers sophisticat…Read more
  •  2
    Evidentialism: Essays in Epistemology (review)
    International Philosophical Quarterly 45 (4): 556-558. 2005.
  •  40
    Sense and Certainty, by Marie McGinn (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (3): 689-693. 1991.
  •  11
    Introduction: The Point and Purpose of Epistemic Evaluation
    In David K. Henderson & John Greco (eds.), Epistemic Evaluation: Purposeful Epistemology, Oxford University Press Uk. pp. 1-28. 2015.
    This introductory chapter proceeds in three parts. The first section characterizes the general approach to epistemology around which the volume revolves—purposeful epistemology—and examines the general motivation for that approach. The guiding idea is that considerations about the point and purpose of epistemic evaluation might fruitfully constrain epistemological theory and yield insights for epistemological reflection. The second section explores the approach by characterizing some important v…Read more
  •  116
    Discrimination and testimonial knowledge
    Episteme 4 (3): 335-351. 2007.
    Sanford Goldberg has called our attention to an interesting problem: How is it that young children can learn from the testimony of their caregivers (their parents, teachers, and nannies, for example) even when the children themselves are undiscriminating consumers of testimony? Part One describes the importance and scope of the problem, showing that it generalizes beyond tots and their caregivers. Part Two considers and rejects several strategies for solving the problem, including Goldberg's own…Read more
  •  104
    This book, first published in 2000, is about the nature of skeptical arguments and their role in philosophical inquiry. John Greco delineates three main theses: that a number of historically prominent skeptical arguments make no obvious mistake, and therefore cannot be easily dismissed; that the analysis of skeptical arguments is philosophically useful and important, and should therefore have a central place in the methodology of philosophy; and that taking skeptical arguments seriously requires…Read more
  •  26
    Warrant: The Current Debate and Warrant and Proper Function
    International Philosophical Quarterly 35 (1): 109-112. 1995.
  •  160
    A Virtue Epistemology (review)
    International Philosophical Quarterly 50 (3): 399-401. 2010.
    Section 1 articulates a genus-species claim: that knowledge is a kind of success from ability. Equivalently: In cases of knowledge, S’s success in believing the truth is attributable to S’s ability. That idea is then applied to questions about the nature and value of knowledge. Section 2 asks what it would take to turn the genus-species claim into a proper theory of knowledge; that is, into informative, necessary and sufficient conditions. That question is raised in the context of an important l…Read more
  •  386
    Knowledge and success from ability
    Philosophical Studies 142 (1). 2009.
    This paper argues that knowledge is an instance of a more general and familiar normative kind—that of success through ability (or success through excellence, or success through virtue). This thesis is developed in the context of three themes prominent in the recent literature: that knowledge attributions are somehow context sensitive; that knowledge is intimately related to practical reasoning; and that one purpose of the concept of knowledge is to flag good sources of information. Wedding these…Read more
  •  452
    A (Different) Virtue Epistemology
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85 (1): 1-26. 2012.
    Section 1 articulates a genus-species claim: that knowledge is a kind of success from ability. Equivalently: In cases of knowledge, S’s success in believing the truth is attributable to S’s ability. That idea is then applied to questions about the nature and value of knowledge. Section 2 asks what it would take to turn the genus-species claim into a proper theory of knowledge; that is, into informative, necessary and sufficient conditions. That question is raised in the context of an important l…Read more