• Themes from Kaplan
    Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 180 (3): 572-573. 1990.
  •  14
    The Problem of the Essential Indexical and Other Essays, Expanded Edition
    Center for the Study of Language and Inf. 2000.
    No word in English is shorter than the word I.' And yet no word is more important in philosophy. When Descartes said I think therefore I am' he produced something that was both about himself and a universal formula. The word I' is called an indexical' because its meaning always depends on who says it. Other examples of indexicals are you,' here,' this' and now.' John Perry discusses how these kinds of words work, and why they express important philosophical thoughts. He shows that indexicals pos…Read more
  •  60
    Wretched subterfuge: a defense of the compatibilism of freedom and natural causation
    Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 84 (2): 93-113. 2010.
  •  22
    Review: David Wiggins, Identity and Spatio-Temporal Continuity (review)
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (3): 447-448. 1970.
  •  21
    The Self Self-knowledge
    Philosophy 1-6. 1998.
    Review Jopling's discussion is carried on with remarkable clarity. His presentation of the diverse philosophical positions is balanced and fair. . . . Self-Knowledge and the Self is a work of excellent, sound scholarship, a most significant contribution. Hazel Barnes, author of Sartre and Flaubert Jopling's book is the most sustained and serious contemporary philosophical reflection on the Delphic injunction Know thyself of which I am aware. Drawing on literature and psychotherapy as well as sol…Read more
  •  25
    Equality and education: Remarks on Kleinberger
    Studies in Philosophy and Education 5 (4): 433-445. 1967.
  •  62
    Davidson's Sentences and Wittgenstein's Builders
    Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 68 (2). 1994.
    Words stand for things of various kinds and for various kinds of things. Because words do this, the sentences made up of words mean what they do, and are capable of expressing our thoughts, our beliefs and conjectures, desires and wishes. This simple idea seems right to me, but it flies in the face of formidable authority. In a famous passage in “Reality without Reference,” Donald Davidson criticizes what he calls the “building-block theory:”.
  •  59
    Situation Theory and its Applications Vol. (edited book)
    with Robin Cooper and Kuniaki Mukai
    CSLI Publications. 1990.
    Preface This volume represents the proceedings of the First Conference on Situation Theory and Its Applications held by CSLI at Asilomar, California, ...
  •  98
    Indexicals
    In Edwards (ed.), The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Supplement, Simon and Schuster Macmillan. pp. 257--258. 1996.
  •  102
  •  16
    The importance of being identical
    In Amélie Rorty (ed.), The Identities of Persons, University of California Press. pp. 67-90. 1976.
  •  700
    A DIALOGUE on PERSONAL IDENTITY and IMMORTALITY This is a record of conversations of Gretchen We/rob, a teacher of philosophy at a small mid- western ...
  •  197
    What is information?
    with David J. Israel
    In Philip P. Hanson (ed.), Information, Language and Cognition, University of British Columbia Press. 1990.
  •  136
    A defense of antecedent physicalism, which argues against the idea that if everything that goes on in the universe is physical, our consciousness and feelings ..
  •  165
  •  205
    Semantic Innocence and Uncompromising Situations
    with Jon Barwise and John Perry
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 6 (1): 387-404. 1981.
  •  1333
    The problem of the essential indexical
    Noûs 13 (1): 3-21. 1979.
    Perry argues that certain sorts of indexicals are 'essential', in the sense that they cannot be eliminated in favor of descriptions. This paper also introduces the influential idea that certain sorts of indexicals play a special role in thought, and have a special connection to action.
  •  419
    Situations and Attitudes
    with Jon Barwise
    MIT Press. 1983.
    This volume tackles the slippery subject of 'meaning'.
  •  119
    In this essay I distinguish three kinds of self-knowledge. I call these three kinds agent-relative knowledge, self-attached knowledge and knowledge of the person one happens to be. These aspects of self-knowledge dier in how the knower or agent is represented. Most of what I say will be applicable to beliefs as well as knowledge, and to other kinds of attitudes and thoughts, such as desire, as well.1 Agent-relative knowledge is knowledge from the perspective of a particular agent. To have this s…Read more
  •  40
    Hintikka on Demonstratives
    Revue Internationale de Philosophie 250 (4): 369-382. 2009.
  •  80
    Executions, Motivations, and Accomplishments
    with David Israel and Syun Tutiya
    Philosophical Review 102 (4). 1993.
    Brutus wanted to kill Caesar. He believed that Caesar was an ordinary mortal, and that, given this, stabbing him (by which we mean plunging a knife into his heart) was a way of killing him. He thought that he could stab Caesar, for he remembered that he had a knife and saw that Caesar was standing next to him on his left, in the Forum. So Brutus was motivated to stab the man to his left. He did so, thereby killing Caesar.
  •  8
    Circumstantial attitudes and benevolent cognition
    In Jeremy Butterfield (ed.), Language, mind and logic, Cambridge University Press. 1986.
    From: _Language, Mind and Logic_, edited by Jeremy Butter?eld. 123.
  •  88
    Using Indexicals
    In Michael Devitt & Richard Hanley (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Language, Wiley-blackwell. pp. 314--334. 2006.
    In this essay I examine how we use indexicals. The key function of indexicals, I claim, is to help the audience --- that is the hearers or readers of the utterance with whom the speaker intends to be communicating---to find supplementary channels of information about the object to which the indexical refers. To keep the discussion manageable, I will oversimplify the epistemology of conversation. I ignore the fact that people sometimes lie and sometimes make mistakes. I talk freely about what one…Read more
  •  166
    Where monsters dwell
    with David Israel
    In Jerry Seligman & Dag Westerstahl (eds.), Logic, Language and Computation, Center For the Study of Language and Inf. pp. 1--303. 1996.
    Kaplan says that monsters violate Principle 2 of his theory. Principle 2 is that indexicals, pure and demonstrative alike, are directly referential. In providing this explanation of there being no monsters, Kaplan feels his theory has an advantage over double-indexing theories like Kamp’s or Segerberg’s (or Stalnaker’s), which either embrace monsters or avoid them only by ad hoc stipulation, in the sharp conceptual distinction it draws between circumstances of evaluation and contexts of utteranc…Read more
  •  89
    Rip Van winkle and other characters
    European Review of Philosophy 2 13-39. 1996.
    In this essay I first review Kaplan’s theory of linguistic character, and then explain and motivate a concept of doxastic character. I then develop some concepts for dealing with the topic of belief retention and then, finally, discuss Rip Van Winkle. I come down on Kaplan’s side with respect to the Frege-inspired strategy, narrowly construed. But I advocate something like the Frege-inspired strategy, if it is construed more broadly. On my view it is remarkably easy to retain a belief, and I thi…Read more
  •  16
    In this paper, I shall defend Russell's view that Mont Blanc, with all of its snow elds, is a component part" or constituent of what is actually asserted when one utters Mont Blanc is more than 4000 meters high," and of what one believes, when one believes that Mont Blanc is 4000 meters high. I also claim, however, that a proposition that does not have Mont Blanc as a constituent plays an important role in the assertion and the belief that Mont Blanc is more than 4000 meters high. Taken somewhat…Read more