•  11
    The Philosophy of Schopenhauer
    Philosophical Review 94 (1): 136. 1985.
  •  26
    Attacking Morality: A Metaethical Project
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 25 (sup1): 221-249. 1995.
  •  120
    9. Self-Deception and Bad Faith
    In Brian P. McLaughlin & Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (eds.), Perspectives on Self-Deception, University of California Press. pp. 207-227. 1988.
  • Marx, Justice and History: A Philosophy and Public Affairs Reader
    with Marshall Cohen, Thomas Nagel, Thomas Scanlon, and Hugo Meynell
    Ethics 93 (4): 792-799. 1983.
  •  31
    Marx’s Critical Anthropology: Three Recent Interpretations
    Review of Metaphysics 26 (1). 1972.
    It is the avowed aim of Avineri’s study to "bring out the ambivalent indebtedness of Marx to the Hegelian tradition." This aim determines the central place of Marx’s concept of man in his discussion; for it was from Hegel and the young Hegelians that Marx drew the anthropological problematic which dominates his early writings. The Hegelian concept of Geist served the young Hegelians as the model for a philosophical conception of man, as a being exhibiting the unique dignity of his rational natur…Read more
  •  76
    Hegel spent most of his life as an educator. Between 1794 and 1800, he was a private tutor, first in Bern, Switzerland, and then in Frankfurt-am-Main. He then began a university career at the University of Jena, which in 1806 was interrupted by the Napoleonic conquest of Prussia, and did not resume for ten years. In the intervening years, he was director of a Gymnasium (or secondary school) in Nuremberg. In 1816, Hegel was appointed professor of philosophy at the University of Heidelberg, then a…Read more
  •  300
    Kant on Duties Regarding Nonrational Nature
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 72 (1). 1998.
    Kant's moral philosophy is grounded on the dignity of humanity as its sole fundamental value, and involves the claim that human beings are to be regarded as the ultimate end of nature. It might be thought that a theory of this kind would be incapable of grounding any conception of our relation to other living things or to the natural world which would value nonhuman creatures or respect humanity's natural environment. This paper criticizes Kant's argumentative strategy for dealing with our dutie…Read more
  •  184
    Fichte's intersubjective I
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 49 (1). 2006.
    The challenge to philosophy of mind for the past two hundred years has been to overcome the Cartesian conception of mind. This essay explores the attempt to do this by J. G. Fichte, especially regarding intersubjectivity or the knowledge of other minds. Fichte provides a transcendental deduction of the concept of the other I, as a condition for experiencing the individuality of our own I. The basis of this argument is the concept of the "summons", which Fichte argues is necessary for us to form …Read more
  • Kant’s Ethical Thought
    Philosophical Quarterly 51 (203): 259-261. 2001.
  •  212
    One of the principal aims of Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals, especially of the Doctrine of Virtue, is to present a taxonomy of our duties as human beings. The basic division of duties is between juridical duties and ethical duties, which determines the division of the Metaphysics of Morals into the Doctrine of Right and the Doctrine of Virtue. Juridical duties are duties that may be coercively enforced from outside the agent, as by the civil or criminal laws, or other social pressures. Ethical dut…Read more
  •  84
    The Free Development of Each collects twelve essays on the history of German philosophy by Allen W. Wood, one of the leading scholars in the field. They explore moral philosophy, politics, society, and history in the works of Kant, Herder, Fichte, Hegel, and Marx, and share the basic theme of freedom, as it appears in morality and in politics.
  •  24
    Kant's Rational Theology.Lectures on Philosophical Theology
    with Ralf Meerbote, I. Kant, and Gertrude M. Clark
    Philosophical Review 89 (2): 285. 1980.
  •  3
    Kant and the intelligibility of evil
    In Sharon Anderson-Gold & Pablo Muchnik (eds.), Kant's Anatomy of Evil, Cambridge University Press. 2009.
  •  12
    Religion and Rational Theology (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 2001.
    This volume collects for the first time in a single volume all of Kant's writings on religion and rational theology. These works were written during a period of conflict between Kant and the Prussian authorities over his religious teachings. His final statement of religion was made after the death of King Frederick William II in 1797. The historical context and progression of this conflict are charted in the general introduction to the volume and in the translators' introductions to particular t…Read more
  •  41
    I_– _Allen W. Wood
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 72 (1): 189-210. 1998.
  •  21
    Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason is a key element of the system of philosophy which Kant introduced with his Critique of Pure Reason, and a work of major importance in the history of Western religious thought. It represents a great philosopher's attempt to spell out the form and content of a type of religion that would be grounded in moral reason and would meet the needs of ethical life. It includes sharply critical and boldly constructive discussions on topics not often treated by …Read more
  •  6
    Karl Marx
    Science and Society 48 (3): 373-376. 1981.
  •  31
    Formal and Transcendental Logic; A Study of Husserl's Formal and Transcendental Logic
    with Edmund Husserl, Dorion Cairns, Suzanne Bachelard, and Lester E. Embree
    Philosophical Review 80 (2): 267. 1971.
  •  3
    Kant's Dialectic
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 5 (4): 595-614. 1975.
    The bulk of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason is divided, in its philosophical content if not its formal organization, into two parts. The first, encompassing the Introduction, the Aesthetic and the Transcendental Analytic, presents a theory of metaphysical knowledge; its source and nature, its proper objects, and its fundamental principles. The second part, contained in the Transcendental Dialectic, is a theory of metaphysical error, illusion, or pseudoknowledge. For various reasons, students of t…Read more
  •  134
    The supreme principle of morality
    In Paul Guyer (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Kant and Modern Philosophy, Cambridge University Press. pp. 342--80. 2006.
    In the Preface to his best known work on moral philosophy, Kant states his purpose very clearly and succinctly: “The present groundwork is, however, nothing more than the search for and establishment of the supreme principle of morality, which already constitutes an enterprise whole in its aim and to be separated from every other moral investigation” (Groundwork 4:392). This paper will deal with the outcome of the first part of this task, namely, Kant’s attempt to formulate the supreme principle…Read more
  •  30
    The latest volume in the Cambridge Histories of Philosophy series, The Cambridge History of Philosophy in the Nineteenth Century brings together twenty-nine leading experts in the field and covers the years 1790-1870. Their twenty-seven chapters provide a comprehensive survey of the period, organizing the material topically. After a brief editor's introduction, it begins with three chapters surveying the background of nineteenth century philosophy: followed by two on logic and mathematics, two o…Read more
  •  12
    Religion and Rational Theology: The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuael Kant (edited book)
    with Immanuel Kant and George Di Giovanni
    Cambridge UP. 1996.
    This Volume contains seven works of Kant, newly translated and edited, with Introductions. What does it mean to orient oneself in thinking? 1786 (Allen Wood) On the miscarriage of all philosophical trials in theodicy. 1791 (George di Giovanni Religion within the boundaries of mere reason. 1793 (George di Giovanni) The end of all things. 1794 (Allen Wood) The conflict of the faculties. 1798 (Mary J. Gregor & Robert Anchor) Preface to Reinhold Bernhard Jackmann's examination of the Kantian Philos…Read more
  •  25
    Kant (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 35 (4): 323-325. 1991.
  •  374
    Marx on right and justice: A reply to Husami
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 8 (3): 267-295. 1979.
    Wood reiterated his previous papers of view - "For Marx, economic, trade or social system of justice or not depends on its mode of production with the established relationship" that Hussami the "justice is not only determined by the mode of production and determined by class position, "the view attributed to Marx is a misconception that Marx was a capitalist from the standards of justice to go after the critique of capitalist society, it is a misreading of Marx's text. In his view, Marx's critiq…Read more
  • Hegel on responsibility for actions and consequences
    In Arto Laitinen & Constantine Sandis (eds.), Hegel on action, Palgrave-macmillan. 2010.
  •  41
    Kant’s Project for Perpetual Peace
    Proceedings of the Eighth International Kant Congress 1 3-18. 1995.
  •  49
    Fichte’s Philosophical Revolution
    Philosophical Topics 19 (2): 1-28. 1991.