•  4
    Erkenntnistheorie
    Metzler. 2002.
    An introduction to epistemology with a focus on different accounts of knowledge, scepticism, belief, truth, rationality and justification, the sources of knowledge.
  •  28
    Begrenzte Erkenntnisse?
    Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 58 (3): 483-489. 2010.
    This is a crtiical discussion of Gabriel's "An den Grenzen der Erkenntnistheorie".
  •  826
    Nozick's defense of closure
    In Kelly Becker & Tim Black (eds.), The Sensitivity Principle in Epistemology, Cambridge University Press. pp. 11--27. 2012.
    This paper argues against common views that at least in many cases Robert Nozick is not forced to deny common closure principles. More importantly, Nozick does not – despite first (and second) appearances and despite his own words – deny closure. On the contrary, he is defending a more sophisticated and complex principle of closure. This principle does remarkably well though it is not without problems. It is surprising how rarely Nozick’s principle of closure has been discussed. He should be see…Read more
  • A Contradiction for Contextualism?
    In Franck Lihoreau & Manuel Rebuschi (eds.), Epistemology, Context, and Formalism, Springer Verlag. pp. 49-57. 2014.
    This discusses a problem for epistemic contextualism having to do with the possibility of evaluating knowledge attributions made in other contexts.
  • Sind die meisten unserer Meinungen wahr? Zu Donald Davidsons 'extended claim'
    Logos. Anales Del Seminario de Metafísica [Universidad Complutense de Madrid, España] 4 116-136. 1997.
    Are our beliefs mostly true? Donald Davidson has proposed some very interesting arguments in favor of his "extended claim" that most our beliefs must be true. The main aim of this paper is to show that Davidson's arguments are not convincing. The most well known of his arguments is the argument of the "omniscient interpreter". The conceivability of a totally ignorant interpreter, however, shows that this argument fails. Davidson offers two more arguments for his extended claim: one of them based…Read more
  •  56
    Knowledge, Assertion, and Inference
    Acta Analytica 29 (4): 487-490. 2014.
    This paper argues that three plausible principles are mutually inconsistent: One ought to assert only what one knows; If it is proper to assert some proposition q, then it is, barring special and not very common circumstances, proper to assert any proposition p from which q has been competently inferred; and Some propositions are both properly assertible and known by competent inference from propositions which one does not know. Each pair of two principles constitutes an argument against the rem…Read more
  •  16
    In a recent paper, Hájek presents the following alleged paradox. You are certain that a cable guy will visit you tomorrow between 8 a.m. and 4 p.m. but you have no further information about when. And you agree to a bet on whether he will come in the morning interval. At first you have no reason to prefer one possibility rather than the other. But you then realise that if you bet on the morning interval, there will certainly be a future time at which you will assign higher probability to an after…Read more
  • Glaube nicht an mich!: Dürfen Moraltheorien Selbst-Auslöschend sein?
    Conceptus: Zeitschrift Fur Philosophie 30 (77): 191-198. 1997.
    A moral theory is "self-effacing" if it tells one not to believe in it. Many people think that the aims of a moral theory (like utilitarianism) can be better reached if it is self-effacing. I argue here that moral theories should not be self-effacing. Except in a special case, the self-effacing character of a theory goes hand in hand with mutually incompatible intentions, practical dilemmas, or pragmatical paradoxes. Hence, if a moral (or non-moral) theory is self-effacing, one should rather giv…Read more
  •  78
    Varieties of contextualism: Standards and descriptions
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 69 (1): 229-246. 2005.
    Most contextualists agree that contexts differ with respect to relevant epistemic standards. In this paper, I discuss the idea that the difference between more modest and stricter standards should be explained in terms of the closeness or remoteness of relevant possible worlds. I argue that there are serious problems with this version of contextualism. In the second part of the paper, I argue for another form of contextualism that has little to do with standards and a lot with the well-known pro…Read more
  •  418
    Meaning and More Meaningful. A Modest Measure
    Journal of Philosophy of Life 5 (3): 33-49. 2015.
    We often describe lives (or parts of lives) as meaningful or as not meaningful. It is also common to characterize them as more or less meaningful. Some lives, we tend to think, are more meaningful than others. But how then can one compare lives with respect to how much meaning they contain? Can one? This paper argues that (i) only a notion of rough equality can be used when comparing different lives with respect to their meaning, and that (ii) the relation of being more meaningful is not transit…Read more
  •  1416
    Epistemic closure
    In Duncan Pritchard & Sven Bernecker (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Epistemology, Routledge. pp. 597--608. 2011.
    This article gives an overview over different principles of epistemic closure, their attractions and their problems.
  •  139
    Reliabilism—modal, probabilistic or contextualist
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 79 (1): 77-89. 2009.
    This paper discusses two versions of reliabilism: modal and probabilistic reliabilism. Modal reliabilism faces the problem of the missing closeness metric for possible worlds while probalistic reliabilism faces the problem of the relevant reference class. Despite the severity of these problems, reliabilism is still very plausible (also for independent reasons). I propose to stick with reliabilism, propose a contextualist (or, alternatively, harmlessly relativist) solution to the above problems a…Read more
  •  216
    For each of the many goals of an agent it is true that the agent wants its realization. Given further very plausible assumptions, one can show that there is no good reason for an agent not to want the realization of all of his goals. However, it seems also true that reaching all of one’s goals would be extremely boring; most human beings would consider such a life not worth living. In this respect, leading a life is like playing some game: A game loses its point if one always easily wins. Human …Read more
  •  61
    Can reliabilists believe in subjective probability?
    Philosophical Quarterly 48 (191): 199-200. 1998.
    According to reliabilist conceptions of knowledge, knowledge implies reliable true belief. Since reliability is an irreducibly probabilistic notion, one's view of knowledge also depends on one's view of probability. If one believes that all probability is subjective probability, knowledge becomes a relativized concept: knowledge is relative to a given body of beliefs of a given person at a given time. Since such a relativized conception of knowledge is extremely implausible and since reliabilism…Read more
  •  271
    On the Inflation of Necessities
    Metaphysica 13 (1): 51-54. 2012.
    This brief paper argues that Kripke’s thesis of the necessity of origin has some implausible consequences
  •  12
    Die Autonomie der Person
    mentis. 2000.
    This book offers a discussion of practical as well as theoretical autonomy.
  • Zur Entstehung von Herrschaft [comment]
    Erwägen Wissen Ethik 17 109-11-. 2006.
    Critical discussion of Maurer's view on power and domination.
  •  53
    Mind and World, John Mcdowell
    Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 2 (1): 135-144. 1998.
    A critical discussion of: Mind and World, John Mcdowell
  •  114
    Is Knowledge Safe?
    American Philosophical Quarterly 45 (1). 2008.
    One of the most interesting accounts of knowledge which have been recently proposed is the safety account of knowledge. According to it, one only knows that p if one's true belief that p could not have easily been false: S believes that p ==> p (where "==>" stands for the subjunctive conditional). This paper presents a counter-example and discusses attempts to fix the problem. It turns out that there is a deeper underlying problem which does not allow for a solution that would help the safety th…Read more
  •  104
    Theory Choice and the Intransitivity of 'Is a Better Theory Than'
    Philosophy of Science 72 (1): 231-240. 2005.
    There is a very plausible principle of the transitivity of justifying reasons. It says that if "p" is better justified than "q" (all things considered) and "q" better than "r", then "p" is better justified than "r" (all things considered). There is a corresponding principle of rational theory choice. Call one theory "a better theory than" another theory if all criteria of theory choice considered (explanatory power, simplicity, empirical adequacy, etc.), the first theory meets the criteria bette…Read more
  • Human dignity seems very important to us. At the same time, the concept ‘human dignity’ is extraordinarily elusive. A good way to approach the questions “What is it?” and “Why is it important?” is to raise another question first: In virtue of what do human beings have human dignity? Speciesism – the idea that human beings have a particular dignity because they are humans – does not seem very convincing. A better answer says that human beings have dignity because and insofar as they are persons. …Read more
  •  101
    Suppose someone hears a loud noise and at the same time sees a yellow flash. It seems hard to deny that the person can experience loudness and yellowness together. However, since loudness is experienced by the auditory sense whereas yellowness is experienced by the visual sense it also seems hard to explain how.
  •  104
    The case for contexualism
    Analysis 70 (1): 149-160. 2010.
    (No abstract is available for this citation).
  •  653
    Knowledge, Practical Reasoning and Action
    Logos and Episteme 3 (1): 7-26. 2012.
    Is knowledge necessary or sufficient or both necessary and sufficient for acceptable practical reasoning and rational action? Several authors (e.g., Williamson, Hawthorne, and Stanley) have recently argued that the answer to these questions is positive. In this paper I present several objections against this view (both in its basic form as well in more developed forms). I also offer a sketch of an alternative view: What matters for the acceptability of practical reasoning in at least many cases …Read more
  •  25
    Defending the One Percent?
    The Harvard Review of Philosophy 21 106-112. 2014.
    This paper discusses and criticizes Greg Mankiw's recent defense of "the one percent".
  •  496
    Philosophy Upside Down?
    Metaphilosophy 44 (5): 579-588. 2013.
    Philip Kitcher recently argued for a reconstruction in philosophy. According to him, the contemporary mainstream of philosophy has deteriorated into something that is of relevance only to a few specialists who communicate with each other in a language nobody else understands. Kitcher proposes to reconstruct philosophy along two axes: a knowledge axis and a value axis. The present article discusses Kitcher's diagnosis as well as his proposal of a therapy. It argues that there are problems with bo…Read more
  • Gibt es Moralische Wahrheiten?
    In Achim Stephan & Klaus Peter Rippe (eds.), Ethik ohne Dogmen. Aufsätze für Günther Patzig, Mentis. pp. 238-255. 2001.
    Are there moral truths? Are (at least some) moral statements or beliefs „true“ or „false“ in the sense of a correspondence theory of truth? Are there moral facts that make those statements or beliefs true or false? In this paper I propose an argument against the idea that moral sentences and beliefs have truth-conditions in that sense. The argument focuses on the semantic and epistemic status of those beliefs and sentences. I also argue that all this does not lead to a subjectivist interpretatio…Read more
  •  22
    Coercion and the Varieties of Free Action
    Ideas Y Valores 52 (122): 31-49. 2003.
    Are we free? What does "freedom" mean here? In the following, I shall only focus with freedom of action. My main thesis is that there is not just one basic type of free action but more. Philosophers, however, tend to assume that there is just one way to act freely. Hence, a more detailed analysis of free action is being called for. I will distinguish between different kinds of free action and discuss the relations between them. The analysis of different types of coercion will lead to a different…Read more
  •  73
    Necessarily Incompatible Consistent Wants
    Acta Analytica 32 (4): 489-490. 2017.
    This paper argues that the wants or desires of a person can be consistent with each other and still necessarily incompatible with each other and for interesting reasons. It is argued here that this problem is not rare and that there is no solution in sight.
  • Begriffe Analysieren?
    In Dirk Koppelberg & Stefan Tolksdorf (eds.), Erkenntnistheorie – wie und wozu?, Mentis. pp. 133-151. 2015.
    This article discusses the very limited definability of philosophically interesting concepts as well as the prospects for the project of conceptual analysis.