•  31
    Self‐Defeating Goals
    with Karin Edvardsson Björnberg and John Cantwell
    Dialectica 70 (4): 491-512. 2016.
    The typical function of goals is to regulate action in a way that furthers goal achievement. Goals are typically set on the assumption that they will help bring the agent closer to the desired state of affairs. However, sometimes endorsement of a goal, or the processes by which the goal is set, can obstruct its achievement. When this happens, the goal is self-defeating. Self-defeating goals are common in both private and social decision-making but have not received much attention by decision the…Read more
  •  31
    Scopes, Options, and Horizons – Key Issues in Decision Structuring
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 21 (2): 259-273. 2018.
    Real-life decision-making often begins with a disorderly decision problem that has to be clarified and systematized before a decision can be made. This is the process of decision structuring that has largely been ignored both in decision theory and applied decision analysis. In this contribution, ten major components of decision structuring are identified, namely the determination of its scope, subdivision, agency, timing, options, control ascriptions, framing, horizon, criteria and restructurin…Read more
  •  31
    Swedish Theses in Philosophy 2009
    Theoria 76 (3): 266-269. 2010.
  •  31
    A Theoria Bibliography
    Theoria 71 (3): 287-289. 2005.
  •  30
    Critical Thinking
    Theoria 85 (1): 3-7. 2019.
  •  30
    The rôle of language in belief revision
    Studia Logica 70 (1). 2002.
    Analytical tools that give precision to the concept of "independence of syntax" are developed in the form of a series of substitutivity principles. These principles are applied in a study of the rôle of language in belief revision theory. It is shown that sets of sentences can be used in models of belief revision to convey more information than what is conveyed by the combined propositional contents of the respective sets. It is argued that it would be unwise to programmatically restrain the use…Read more
  •  30
    Similarity semantics and minimal changes of belief
    Erkenntnis 37 (3): 401-429. 1992.
    Different similarity relations on sets are introduced, and their logical properties are investigated. Close relationships are shown to hold between similarity relations that are based on symmetrical difference and operators of belief contraction that are based on relational selection functions. Two new rationality criteria for minimal belief contraction, the maximizing property and the reducing property, are proposed
  •  30
    Reconstruction of Contraction Operators
    Erkenntnis 81 (1): 185-199. 2016.
    An operator of belief change is reconstructible as another such operator if and only if any outcome that can be obtained with the former can also be obtained with the latter. Two operators are mutually reconstructible if they generate exactly the same set of outcomes. The relations of reconstructibility among fifteen operators of contraction, including the common AGM contraction operators, are completely characterized. Furthermore, the additional such relations are characterized that arise if al…Read more
  •  30
    Experiments: Why and How?
    Science and Engineering Ethics 22 (3): 613-632. 2016.
    An experiment, in the standard scientific sense of the term, is a procedure in which some object of study is subjected to interventions that aim at obtaining a predictable outcome or at least predictable aspects of the outcome. The distinction between an experiment and a non-experimental observation is important since they are tailored to different epistemic needs. Experimentation has its origin in pre-scientific technological experiments that were undertaken in order to find the best technologi…Read more
  •  29
    Bootstrap Contraction
    Studia Logica 101 (5): 1013-1029. 2013.
    We can often specify how we would contract by a certain sentence by saying that this contraction would coincide with some other contraction that we know how to perform. We can for instance clarify that our contraction by p&q would coincide with our contraction by p, or by q, or by {p, q}. In a framework where the set of potential outcomes is known, some contractions are “self-evident” in the sense that there is only one serious candidate that can be the outcome of such a contraction. Contraction…Read more
  •  29
    Safe Design
    Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology 10 (1): 45-52. 2006.
    Safety is an essential ethical requirement in engineering design. Strategies for safe design are used not only to reduce estimated probabilities of injuries but also to cope with hazards and eventualities that cannot be assigned meaningful probabilities. The notion of safe design has important ethical dimensions, such as that of determining the responsibility that a designer has for future uses of the designed object.
  •  29
    The Moral Oracle’s Test
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17 (4): 643-651. 2014.
    When presented with a situation involving an agent’s choice between alternative actions, a moral oracle says what the agent is allowed to do. The oracle bases her advice on some moral theory, but the nature of that theory is not known by us. The moral oracle’s test consists in determining whether a series of questions to the oracle can be so constructed that her answers will reveal which of two given types of theories she adheres to. The test can be applied to moral theories in order to determin…Read more
  •  29
    How to make up one's mind
    with Li Zhang
    Logic Journal of the IGPL 23 (4): 705-717. 2015.
  •  28
    This book provides a critical examination of how the choice of what to believe is represented in the standard model of belief change. In particular the use of possible worlds and infinite remainders as objects of choice is critically examined. Descriptors are introduced as a versatile tool for expressing the success conditions of belief change, addressing both local and global descriptor revision. The book presents dynamic descriptors such as Ramsey descriptors that convey how an agent’s beliefs…Read more
  •  28
    Has Philosophy Failed?
    Theoria 88 (1): 3-7. 2022.
    Theoria, Volume 88, Issue 1, Page 3-7, February 2022.
  •  28
    Cooperation in Philosophy
    Theoria 65 (1): 1-2. 1999.
  •  28
    Editorial: Philosophical Terminology
    Theoria 71 (4): 291-293. 2005.
  •  28
    Mill’s Circle(s) of Liberty
    Social Theory and Practice 41 (4): 734-749. 2015.
    J.S. Mill’s advocacy of liberty was based only in part on his harm principle. He also endorsed two other principles that considerably extend the scope of liberty: first, a principle of individual liberty that is based on the value of positive freedom and of developing individuality, and second, a principle of free trade or economic freedom that is based on the value of economic efficiency. An analysis is offered of how these three principles are combined in Mill’s account of liberty and how they…Read more
  •  28
    Technology and Mathematics
    Philosophy and Technology 33 (1): 117-139. 2020.
    In spite of their practical importance, the connections between technology and mathematics have not received much scholarly attention. This article begins by outlining how the technology–mathematics relationship has developed, from the use of simple aide-mémoires for counting and arithmetic, via the use of mathematics in weaving, building and other trades, and the introduction of calculus to solve technological problems, to the modern use of computers to solve both technological and mathematical…Read more
  •  28
    Recovery and epistemic residue
    Journal of Logic, Language and Information 8 (4): 421-428. 1999.
    Two recent defences of the recovery postulate for contraction of belief sets are analyzed. It is concluded that recovery is defensible as a by-product of a formalization that is idealized in the sense of being simplified for the sake of clarity. However, recovery does not seem to be a required feature of the doxastic behaviour of ideal (perfectly rational) agents. It is reasonable to expect that there should be epistemic residues (remnants of rejected beliefs), but not that these should always s…Read more
  •  27
    Philosophical Plagiarism under the Spotlight
    Theoria 85 (2): 61-68. 2019.
  •  27
    Ethical conflicts in patient-centred care
    with Barbro Fröding
    Sage Publications: Clinical Ethics. forthcoming.
    Clinical Ethics, Ahead of Print. It could hardly be denied that healthcare should be patient-centred. However, some of the practices commonly described as patient-centred care may have ethically problematic consequences. This article identifies and discusses twelve ethical conflicts that may arise in the application of person-centred care. The conflicts concern e.g. privacy, autonomous decision-making, safeguarding medical quality, and maintaining professional egalitarianism as well as equality …Read more
  •  27
    The revenger's paradox
    Philosophical Studies 61 (3). 1991.
  •  27
    Against philosophical anorexia
    Theoria 67 (3): 187-188. 2001.
  •  27
    Philosophy as a Unifying Discipline
    Theoria 67 (2): 93-95. 2001.
  •  27
    Why Publish At All?
    Theoria 84 (1): 1-3. 2018.
  •  27