•  59
    The false promises of risk analysis
    Ratio 6 (1): 16-26. 1993.
    The relatively new discipline of risk analysis promises to provide objective guidance in some of the most controversial issues in modern high‐technology societies. Four conditions are discussed that must be satisfied for this promise to be fulfilled. Since none of these conditions is satisfied, risk analysis does not keep its promise. In its attempts to reduce genuinely political issues to technocratic calculations, it neglects many of the factors that should influence decisions on risk acceptan…Read more
  •  647
    This text is a non-technical overview of modern decision theory. It is intended for university students with no previous acquaintance with the subject, and was primarily written for the participants of a course on risk analysis at Uppsala University in 1994.
  •  36
    The Ethics of Biobanks
    Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 13 (4): 319-326. 2004.
    Due to modern biochemistry and, in particular, recent developments in genomics, proteomics, and bioinformatics, human samples have become the most important raw materials for advancement in the health sciences. Such material has been at the center of fundamental biomedical research for a long time. What is new is its increased usefulness in research with direct clinical relevance, such as the development of drugs. Because of the larger commercial involvement in such research, this has also led t…Read more
  •  51
    Book reviews (review)
    with Connie Xiaokang Yu, Maria Luisa Dalla Chiara, Fraser MacBride, Dale Jacquette, Maarten Marx, and Stig Alstrup Rasmussen
    Studia Logica 77 (1): 619-624. 2004.
  •  20
    Back to Basics: Belief Revision Through Direct Selection
    Studia Logica 107 (5): 887-915. 2019.
    Traditionally, belief change is modelled as the construction of a belief set that satisfies a success condition. The success condition is usually that a specified sentence should be believed or not believed. Furthermore, most models of belief change employ a select-and-intersect strategy. This means that a selection is made among primary objects that satisfy the success condition, and the intersection of the selected objects is taken as outcome of the operation. However, the select-and-intersect…Read more
  •  31
    Swedish Theses in Philosophy 2009
    Theoria 76 (3): 266-269. 2010.
  •  37
    Defining "good" and "bad" in terms of "better"
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 31 (1): 136-149. 1989.
  •  29
    How to make up one's mind
    with Li Zhang
    Logic Journal of the IGPL 23 (4): 705-717. 2015.
  •  16
    Anonymous Philosophical Communication
    Theoria 84 (2): 113-119. 2018.
  •  70
    The Ethics of Enabling Technology
    Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 16 (3): 257-267. 2007.
    Healthcare depends increasingly on advanced medical technology. In addition, other forms of technology contribute to determine how our lives are influenced by disease and disability. The extent to which persons with impaired bodily functions are forced to live their lives differently than other people depends to a large part on a variety of technologies, from wheelchairs to computer interfaces, from hearing aids to garage doors. This wide-ranging influence of technology has important ethical asp…Read more
  •  17
    The difference model of voting
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 33 (4): 576-592. 1992.
  •  61
    Zombie Arguments and the Progress of Philosophy
    Theoria 82 (3): 215-216. 2016.
  •  78
    What's new isn't always best
    Theoria 63 (1-2): 1-13. 1997.
  •  57
    What is ceteris paribus preference?
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 25 (3). 1996.
    A general format is introduced for deriving preferences over states of affairs from preferences over a set of contextually complete alternatives. Formal results are given both for this general format and for a specific instance of it that is a plausible explication of ceteris paribus preference
  •  11
    Philosophical craftsmanship
    Metaphilosophy 25 (4): 316-325. 1994.
  •  71
    Safety is more than the antonym of risk
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 23 (4). 2006.
    abstract Even though much research has been devoted to studies of safety, the concept of safety is in itself under‐theorised, especially concerning its relation to epistemic uncertainty. In this paper we propose a conceptual analysis of safety. The paper explores the distinc‐tion between absolute and relative safety, as well as that between objective and subjective safety. Four potential dimensions of safety are discussed, viz. harm, probability, epistemic uncertainty, and control. The first thr…Read more
  •  42
    Writing Our Own History
    Theoria 77 (2): 101-103. 2011.
  •  112
    What is philosophy of risk?
    Theoria 62 (1-2): 169-186. 1996.
  •  46
    In the first part of this paper, I clear the ground from frequent misconceptions of the relationship between fact and value by examining some uses of the adjective “natural” in ethical controversies. Such uses bear evidence to our “natural” tendency to regard nature as the source of ethical norms. I then try to account for the origins of this tendency by offering three related explanations, the most important of which is evolutionistic: if any behaviour that favours our equilibrium with the envi…Read more
  •  101
    What is stability?
    with G. Helgesson
    Synthese 136 (2). 2003.
    Although stability is a central notion in several academic disciplines, the parallelsremain unexplored since previous discussions of the concept have been almostexclusively subject-specific. In the literature we have found three basic conceptsof stability, that we call constancy, robustness, and resilience. They are all foundin both the natural and the social sciences. To analyze the three concepts we introducea general formal framework in which stability relates to transitions between states. I…Read more
  •  161
    Privacy at work – ethical criteria
    with Anders J. Persson
    Journal of Business Ethics 42 (1). 2003.
    New technologies and practices, such as drug testing, genetic testing, and electronic surveillance infringe upon the privacy of workers on workplaces. We argue that employees have a prima facie right to privacy, but this right can be overridden by competing moral principles that follow, explicitly or implicitly, from the contract of employment. We propose a set of criteria for when intrusions into an employee''s privacy are justified. Three types of justification are specified, namely those that…Read more
  •  27
    Why Publish At All?
    Theoria 84 (1): 1-3. 2018.
  •  104
    Values in pure and applied science
    Foundations of Science 12 (3): 257-268. 2007.
    In pure science, the standard approach to non-epistemic values is to exclude them as far as possible from scientific deliberations. When science is applied to practical decisions, non-epistemic values cannot be excluded. Instead, they have to be combined with scientific information in a way that leads to practically optimal decisions. A normative model is proposed for the processing of information in both pure and applied science. A general-purpose corpus of scientific knowledge, with high entry…Read more
  •  35
    Protecting people in research: A comparison between biomedical and traffic research (review)
    with Sara Svensson
    Science and Engineering Ethics 13 (1): 99-115. 2007.
    Traffic research shares a fundamental dilemma with other areas of empirical research in which humans are potentially put at risk. Research is justified because it can improve safety in the long run. Nevertheless, people can be harmed in the research situation. Hence, we need to balance short-term risks against long-term safety improvements, much as in other areas of research with human subjects. In this paper we focus on ethical issues that arise when human beings are directly affected in the pe…Read more
  •  75
    Modern belief revision theory is based to a large extent on partial meet contraction that was introduced in the seminal article by Carlos Alchourrón, Peter Gärdenfors, and David Makinson that appeared in 1985. In the same year, Alchourrón and Makinson published a significantly different approach to the same problem, called safe contraction. Since then, safe contraction has received much less attention than partial meet contraction. The present paper summarizes the current state of knowledge on s…Read more
  •  14
    Who Should be Author?
    Theoria 83 (2): 99-102. 2017.
  •  58
    What is technological science?
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 38 (3): 523-527. 2007.
    The technological sciences have at least six defining characteristics that distinguish them from the other sciences. They have human-made rather than natural objects as their study objects, include the practice of engineering design, define their study objects in functional terms, evaluate these study objects with category-specified value statements, employ less far-reaching idealizations than the natural sciences, and do not need an exact mathematical solution when a sufficiently close approxim…Read more
  •  46
    Bioethics in Sweden
    with Barbro Björkman
    Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 15 (3): 285-293. 2006.
    Sweden is probably one of the most secularized nations in the world. Therefore religious arguments tend to play a smaller role in the public bioethical debate than in most other countries. Issues such as abortion, stem-cell research, and therapeutic cloning have been far less controversial in Sweden than elsewhere. Instead, other issues have dominated recent bioethical debates in Sweden, in particular those concerning privacy and the control over biological information about individuals