• Det filosofiska hantverket
    Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift 2. 1992.
  •  17
    Book review (review)
    Erkenntnis 45 (1): 419-422. 1996.
  •  1
  •  1
    Defining pseudo-science
    Philosophia Naturalis 33 (1): 169-176. 1996.
  •  25
    Cutting the Gordian Knot of Demarcation
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 23 (3): 237-243. 2009.
    A definition of pseudoscience is proposed, according to which a statement is pseudoscientific if and only if it (1) pertains to an issue within the domains of science, (2) is not epistemically warranted, and (3) is part of a doctrine whose major proponents try to create the impression that it is epistemically warranted. This approach has the advantage of separating the definition of pseudoscience from the justification of the claim that science represents the most epistemically warranted stateme…Read more
  •  2
    Book review (review)
    Erkenntnis 64 (3): 419-422. 2006.
  •  5
    Eradication
    Journal of Applied Logic 10 (1): 75-84. 2012.
  •  16
    Descriptor Revision
    Studia Logica 102 (5): 955-980. 2014.
    A descriptor is a set of sentences that are truth-functional combinations of expressions of the form \ , where \ is a metalinguistic belief predicate and p a sentence in the object language in which beliefs are expressed. Descriptor revision ) is an operation of belief change that takes us from a belief set K to a new belief set \ where \ is a descriptor representing the success condition. Previously studied operations of belief change are special cases of descriptor revision, hence sentential r…Read more
  • Changes in Preferences
    Theory and Decision 38 (1). 1995.
  •  5
    Coherence in Epistemology and Belief Revision
    Philosophical Studies 128 (1): 93-108. 2006.
    A general theory of coherence is proposed, in which systemic and relational coherence are shown to be interdefinable. When this theory is applied to sets of sentences, it turns out that logical closure obscures the distinctions that are needed for a meaningful analysis of coherence. It is concluded that references to “all beliefs” in coherentist phrases such as “all beliefs support each other” have to be modified so that merely derived beliefs are excluded. Therefore, in order to avoid absurd co…Read more
  •  3
    Do we Need a Special Ethics for Research?
    Science and Engineering Ethics 17 (1): 21-29. 2011.
    Research is subject to more stringent ethical requirements than most other human activities, and a procedure that is otherwise allowed may be forbidden in research. Hence, risk-taking is more restricted in scientific research than in most non-research contexts, and privacy is better protected in scientific questionnaires than in marketing surveys. Potential arguments for this difference are scrutinized. The case in its favour appears to be weak. A stronger case can be made in favour of a differe…Read more
  •  4
    Changing the Scientific Corpus
    In Erik J. Olson Sebastian Enqvist (ed.), Belief Revision meets Philosophy of Science, Springer. pp. 43. 2011.
  •  6
    Changes of disjunctively closed bases
    Journal of Logic, Language and Information 2 (4): 255-284. 1993.
    An operator of contraction for a belief set (a theory) can be obtained by assigning to it a belief base and an operator of partial meet contraction for that base. It is argued that closure of the base under disjunction is an intuitively reasonable condition. Axiomatic characterizations are given of the contractions of belief sets that can be generated by (various types of) partial meet contraction on disjunctively closed bases. The corresponding revision operators are also characterized. Finally…Read more
  •  7
    Rationality postulates for preferences are developed from two basic decision theoretic principles, namely: (1) the logic of preference is determined by paradigmatic cases in which preferences are choice-guiding, and (2) excessive comparison costs should be avoided. It is shown how the logical requirements on preferences depend on the structure of comparison costs. The preference postulates necessary for choice guidance in a single decision problem are much weaker than completeness and transitivi…Read more
  •  3
    But what should I do?
    Philosophia 27 (3-4): 433-440. 1999.
  •  4
    Cooperation in Philosophy
    Theoria 65 (1): 1-2. 1999.
  •  5
    Do we need second-order probabilities?
    Dialectica 62 (4): 525-533. 2008.
    Although it has often been claimed that all the information contained in second-order probabilities can be contained in first-order probabilities, no practical recipe for the elimination of second-order probabilities without loss of information seems to have been presented. Here, such an elimination method is introduced for repeatable events. However, its application comes at the price of losses in cognitive realism. In spite of their technical eliminability, second-order probabilities are usefu…Read more
  •  7
    Coping with the Unpredictable Effects of Future Technologies
    Philosophy and Technology 24 (2): 137-149. 2011.
    Available methods such as technology assessment and risk analysis have failed to predict the effects of technological choices. We need to give up the futile predictive ambitions of previous approaches and instead base decisions on systematic studies of alternative future developments. It will then be necessary to cope with mere possibility arguments, i.e., arguments in which a conclusion is drawn from a mere possibility that a course of action may have certain consequences. A five-step procedure…Read more
  •  4
    Book review (review)
    Erkenntnis 41 (1): 419-422. 1994.
  •  3
    Defining technical function
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 37 (1): 19-22. 2006.
  • Church's Thesis as an Empirical Hypothesis
    International Logic Review 16 96-101. 1985.
  •  1
    Against philosophical anorexia
    Theoria 67 (3): 187-188. 2001.
  •  11
    A Theoria Bibliography: Swedish Theses in Philosophy 2003
    Theoria 70 (2-3): 303-305. 2004.