•  90
    Welfare, Justice, and Pareto Efficiency
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 7 (4): 361-380. 2004.
    In economic analysis, it is usually assumed that each individuals well-being (mental welfare) depends on her or his own resources (material welfare). A typology is provided of the ways in which one persons well-being may depend on the material resources of other persons. When such dependencies are taken into account, standard Paretian analysis of welfare needs to be modified. Pareto efficiency on the level of material resources need not coincide with Pareto efficiency on the level of well-being.…Read more
  •  60
    Who Can Write My Dissertation for Me?
    Theoria 81 (4): 283-288. 2015.
  •  6
    Levi Contractions and AGM Contractions: A Comparison
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 36 (1): 103-119. 1995.
    A representation theorem is obtained for contraction operators that are based on Levi's recent proposal that selection functions should be applied to the set of saturatable contractions, rather than to maximal subsets as in the AGM framework. Furthermore, it is shown that Levi's proposal to base the selection on a weakly monotonic measure of informational value guarantees the satisfaction of both of Gärdenfors' supplementary postulates for contraction. These results indicate that Levi has succee…Read more
  •  51
    Order-Independent Transformative Decision Rules
    Synthese 147 (2): 323-342. 2005.
    A transformative decision rule alters the representation of a decision problem, either by changing the set of alternative acts or the set of states of the world taken into consideration, or by modifying the probability or value assignments. A set of transformative decision rules is order-independent in case the order in which the rules are applied is irrelevant. The main result of this paper is an axiomatic characterization of order-independent transformative decision rules, based on a single ax…Read more
  •  57
    Wedberg on philosophical analysis
    Theoria 76 (2): 97-99. 2010.
    No Abstract
  •  1
  •  3
    Methodological Pluralism in Philosophy
    Theoria 76 (3): 189-191. 2010.
  •  12
    Extended antipaternalism
    Journal of Medical Ethics 31 (2): 97-100. 2005.
    Extended antipaternalism means the use of antipaternalist arguments to defend activities that harm (consenting) others. As an example, a smoker’s right to smoke is often invoked in defence of the activities of tobacco companies. It can, however, be shown that antipaternalism in the proper sense does not imply such extended antipaternalism. We may therefore approve of Mill’s antipaternalist principle (namely, that the only reason to interfere with someone’s behaviour is to protect others from har…Read more
  •  61
    Zombie Arguments and the Progress of Philosophy
    Theoria 82 (3): 215-216. 2016.
  •  9
    What's new isn't always best
    Theoria 63 (1-2): 1-13. 1997.
  •  5
    What is ceteris paribus preference?
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 25 (3). 1996.
    A general format is introduced for deriving preferences over states of affairs from preferences over a set of contextually complete alternatives. Formal results are given both for this general format and for a specific instance of it that is a plausible explication of ceteris paribus preference
  •  5
    Philosophical craftsmanship
    Metaphilosophy 25 (4): 316-325. 1994.
  •  11
    Safety is more than the antonym of risk
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 23 (4). 2006.
    abstract Even though much research has been devoted to studies of safety, the concept of safety is in itself under‐theorised, especially concerning its relation to epistemic uncertainty. In this paper we propose a conceptual analysis of safety. The paper explores the distinc‐tion between absolute and relative safety, as well as that between objective and subjective safety. Four potential dimensions of safety are discussed, viz. harm, probability, epistemic uncertainty, and control. The first thr…Read more
  •  2
    Writing Our Own History
    Theoria 77 (2): 101-103. 2011.
  •  2
    What is philosophy of risk?
    Theoria 62 (1-2): 169-186. 1996.
  •  49
    In the first part of this paper, I clear the ground from frequent misconceptions of the relationship between fact and value by examining some uses of the adjective “natural” in ethical controversies. Such uses bear evidence to our “natural” tendency to regard nature as the source of ethical norms. I then try to account for the origins of this tendency by offering three related explanations, the most important of which is evolutionistic: if any behaviour that favours our equilibrium with the envi…Read more
  •  7
    What is stability?
    with G. Helgesson
    Synthese 136 (2). 2003.
    Although stability is a central notion in several academic disciplines, the parallelsremain unexplored since previous discussions of the concept have been almostexclusively subject-specific. In the literature we have found three basic conceptsof stability, that we call constancy, robustness, and resilience. They are all foundin both the natural and the social sciences. To analyze the three concepts we introducea general formal framework in which stability relates to transitions between states. I…Read more
  •  9
    Privacy at work – ethical criteria
    with Anders J. Persson
    Journal of Business Ethics 42 (1). 2003.
    New technologies and practices, such as drug testing, genetic testing, and electronic surveillance infringe upon the privacy of workers on workplaces. We argue that employees have a prima facie right to privacy, but this right can be overridden by competing moral principles that follow, explicitly or implicitly, from the contract of employment. We propose a set of criteria for when intrusions into an employee''s privacy are justified. Three types of justification are specified, namely those that…Read more
  •  27
    Why Publish At All?
    Theoria 84 (1): 1-3. 2018.
  •  11
    Values in pure and applied science
    Foundations of Science 12 (3): 257-268. 2007.
    In pure science, the standard approach to non-epistemic values is to exclude them as far as possible from scientific deliberations. When science is applied to practical decisions, non-epistemic values cannot be excluded. Instead, they have to be combined with scientific information in a way that leads to practically optimal decisions. A normative model is proposed for the processing of information in both pure and applied science. A general-purpose corpus of scientific knowledge, with high entry…Read more
  •  6
    Protecting people in research: A comparison between biomedical and traffic research (review)
    with Sara Svensson
    Science and Engineering Ethics 13 (1): 99-115. 2007.
    Traffic research shares a fundamental dilemma with other areas of empirical research in which humans are potentially put at risk. Research is justified because it can improve safety in the long run. Nevertheless, people can be harmed in the research situation. Hence, we need to balance short-term risks against long-term safety improvements, much as in other areas of research with human subjects. In this paper we focus on ethical issues that arise when human beings are directly affected in the pe…Read more
  •  83
    Modern belief revision theory is based to a large extent on partial meet contraction that was introduced in the seminal article by Carlos Alchourrón, Peter Gärdenfors, and David Makinson that appeared in 1985. In the same year, Alchourrón and Makinson published a significantly different approach to the same problem, called safe contraction. Since then, safe contraction has received much less attention than partial meet contraction. The present paper summarizes the current state of knowledge on s…Read more
  •  30
    The Moral Oracle’s Test
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17 (4): 643-651. 2014.
    When presented with a situation involving an agent’s choice between alternative actions, a moral oracle says what the agent is allowed to do. The oracle bases her advice on some moral theory, but the nature of that theory is not known by us. The moral oracle’s test consists in determining whether a series of questions to the oracle can be so constructed that her answers will reveal which of two given types of theories she adheres to. The test can be applied to moral theories in order to determin…Read more
  •  1
    Twelve theses on the use of logic in moral philosophy
    Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research 27 (2). 2010.
    Logic is a useful tool in moral philosophy, since it provides us with precise tools to study the structure of moral concepts and moral argumentation. Twelve theses on the use of logic in moral philosophy are put forward, emphasizing the possibilities but also pointing out some of the pitfalls.
  •  20
    The Paradox of Useful Research
    Theoria 83 (1): 1-3. 2017.
  •  693
    Avdelningen för Filosofi, Institutionen för Filosofi och Teknikhistoria, KTH, Stockholm. Detta dokument får tills vidare fritt användas och kopieras.
  •  44
    The Ethics of Doing Ethics
    Science and Engineering Ethics 23 (1): 105-120. 2017.
    Ethicists have investigated ethical problems in other disciplines, but there has not been much discussion of the ethics of their own activities. Research in ethics has many ethical problems in common with other areas of research, and it also has problems of its own. The researcher’s integrity is more precarious than in most other disciplines, and therefore even stronger procedural checks are needed to protect it. The promotion of some standpoints in ethical issues may be socially harmful, and ev…Read more
  •  12
    The Uses and Misuses of Philosophical Scepticism
    Theoria 83 (3): 169-174. 2017.