•  81
    Philosophical plagiarism
    Theoria 74 (2): 97-101. 2008.
    No Abstract
  •  32
    Replacement—A Sheffer Stroke for Belief Change
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 38 (2): 127-149. 2009.
    By replacement is meant an operation that replaces one sentence by another in a belief set. Replacement can be used as a kind of Sheffer stroke for belief change, since contraction, revision, and expansion can all be defined in terms of it. Replacement can also be defined either in terms of contraction or in terms of revision. Close connections are shown to hold between axioms for replacement and axioms for contraction and revision. Partial meet replacement is axiomatically characterized. It is …Read more
  •  2
    Risk Analysis
    In Jan Kyrre Berg Olsen Friis, Stig Andur Pedersen & Vincent F. Hendricks (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Technology, Wiley-blackwell. 2009.
  •  839
    Philosophical Perspectives on Risk
    Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology 8 (1): 10-35. 2004.
    In non-technical contexts, the word “risk” refers, often rather vaguely, to situations in which it is possible but not certain that some undesirable event will occur. In technical contexts, the word has many uses and specialized meanings. The most common ones are the following.
  •  57
    Semi-revision
    Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 7 (1-2): 151-175. 1997.
    ABSTRACT Semi-revision is a mode of belief change that differs from revision in that the input sentence is not always accepted. A constructive approach to semi-revision is proposed. It requires an efficient treatment of local inconsistencies, which is more easily obtainable in belief base models than in belief set models. Axiomatic characterizations of two semi-revision operators are reported.
  • Risker och rationalitet
    Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift 8 (4): 1. 1987.
  •  52
    Repertoire Contraction
    Journal of Logic, Language and Information 22 (1): 1-21. 2013.
    The basic assumption of repertoire contraction is that only some of the logically closed subsets of the original belief set are viable as contraction outcomes. Contraction takes the form of choosing directly among these viable outcomes, rather than among cognitively more far-fetched objects such as possible worlds or maximal consistent subsets of the original belief set. In this first investigation of repertoire contraction, postulates for various variants of the operation are introduced. Necess…Read more
  •  35
    Progress in Philosophy – a Centennial Perspective
    Theoria 82 (2): 101-103. 2016.
  •  65
    Past Probabilities
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 51 (2): 207-223. 2010.
    The probability that a fair coin tossed yesterday landed heads is either 0 or 1, but the probability that it would land heads was 0.5. In order to account for the latter type of probabilities, past probabilities, a temporal restriction operator is introduced and axiomatically characterized. It is used to construct a representation of conditional past probabilities. The logic of past probabilities turns out to be strictly weaker than the logic of standard probabilities
  •  25
    Radiation Protection—Sorting Out the Arguments
    Philosophy and Technology 24 (3): 363-368. 2011.
    This is a response to an article by Wade Allison in which he argues that we should accept drastically higher doses of ionizing radiation than what we currently do. He employs four arguments in defence of his position: comparisons with background radiation, the positive experiences of radiotherapy, the presence of biological defence mechanisms against radiation, and a concession by Swedish authorities that their approach to reindeer meat after the Chernobyl fallout was unnecessarily strict. It is…Read more
  •  31
    Reconstruction of Contraction Operators
    Erkenntnis 81 (1): 185-199. 2016.
    An operator of belief change is reconstructible as another such operator if and only if any outcome that can be obtained with the former can also be obtained with the latter. Two operators are mutually reconstructible if they generate exactly the same set of outcomes. The relations of reconstructibility among fifteen operators of contraction, including the common AGM contraction operators, are completely characterized. Furthermore, the additional such relations are characterized that arise if al…Read more
  •  34
    Precision in Philosophy
    Theoria 78 (4): 273-275. 2012.
  • Självförverkligande - begrepp utan mening?
    Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift 3 (3): 1. 1982.
  • Recension av Amartya Sen: "Kollektiva beslut och social välfärd"
    Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift 10 (1): 28. 1989.
  •  37
    Praxis relevance in science
    Foundations of Science 12 (2): 139-154. 2006.
    Science is praxis relevant to the extent that it guides goal-directed action by telling us how to act in order to achieve the goals. Investigations aiming at high praxis relevance are performed in various disciplines under names such as clinical trials, evaluation research, intervention research and social experiments. In this contribution, the notion of (direct) praxis relevance is delineated, and it is distinguished from related properties of science such as those of being applied and being pr…Read more
  •  252
    Philosophical problems in cost–benefit analysis
    Economics and Philosophy 23 (2): 163-183. 2007.
    Cost–benefit analysis (CBA) is much more philosophically interesting than has in general been recognized. Since it is the only well-developed form of applied consequentialism, it is a testing-ground for consequentialism and for the counterfactual analysis that it requires. Ten classes of philosophical problems that affect the practical performance of cost–benefit analysis are investigated: topic selection, dependence on the decision perspective, dangers of super synopticism and undue centralizat…Read more
  •  1
    Book Review: The Future for Philosophy, ed. by Brian Leiter (review)
    Disputatio 1 (20): 346-348. 2006.
  •  24
    Review of Hans Rott, Change, choice and inference: A study of belief revision and nonmonotonic reasoning (review)
    Studia Logica: An International Journal for Symbolic Logic 77 145-147. 2004.
  •  28
    Recovery and epistemic residue
    Journal of Logic, Language and Information 8 (4): 421-428. 1999.
    Two recent defences of the recovery postulate for contraction of belief sets are analyzed. It is concluded that recovery is defensible as a by-product of a formalization that is idealized in the sense of being simplified for the sake of clarity. However, recovery does not seem to be a required feature of the doxastic behaviour of ideal (perfectly rational) agents. It is reasonable to expect that there should be epistemic residues (remnants of rejected beliefs), but not that these should always s…Read more
  •  54
    Risk
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
  •  154
    Science denial as a form of pseudoscience
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 63 39-47. 2017.
  •  50
    Predatory Open Access
    Theoria 80 (4): 289-291. 2014.
  •  26
    Reversing “Research Exceptionalism”
    American Journal of Bioethics 10 (8): 66-67. 2010.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  • New operators for theory change
    Theoria 55 (2): 114. 1989.
  •  48
    Money-pumps, self-torturers and the demons of real life
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (4). 1993.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  53
    Philosophy and Intercultural Dialogue
    Theoria 79 (2): 93-95. 2013.
  •  65
    Philosophy and Public Policy
    Theoria 78 (2): 89-92. 2012.