•  32
    Photography and the “Picturesque Agent”
    Critical Inquiry 38 (4): 855-869. 2012.
    Even as art theory and analytic philosophy have failed to connect in their studies of photography, the two disciplines have joined in tying conceptions of the specific character of photography to ideas about automaticity and agency.1 In rough caricature, the philosopher reasons: “An item is a work of art only insofar as it is the product of agency, so a photograph is not an art work insofar it is not the product of artistic agency. After all, in Lady Eastlake's colorful words, the ‘obedience of …Read more
  •  121
    Aesthetic Experts, Guides to Value
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 73 (3): 235-246. 2015.
    A theory of aesthetic value should explain the performance of aesthetic experts, for aesthetic experts are agents who track aesthetic value. Aesthetic empiricism, the theory that an item's aesthetic value is its power to yield aesthetic pleasure, suggests that aesthetic experts are best at locating aesthetic pleasure, especially given aesthetic internalism, the view that aesthetic reasons always have motivating force. Problems with empiricism and internalism open the door to an alternative. Aest…Read more
  •  54
    A philosophy of mass art (review)
    Philosophical Review 109 (4): 614-617. 2000.
    The chief sources of aesthetic experience for most people around the world are now the mass broadcasting and recording technologies. Yet analytic aesthetics has had little to say about mass art. Recent accounts of art and the aesthetic, while accommodating the consensus concerning central cases, are largely propelled by problem cases drawn from the avant-garde, and one wonders what the effect will be of adding works of mass art to the equation. One also wonders whether making room for mass art w…Read more
  •  128
    Art Without ‘Art’
    British Journal of Aesthetics 47 (1): 1-15. 2007.
    Some argue that there is no art in some non-Western cultures because members of those cultures have no concept of art. Others argue that members of some non-Western cultures have concepts of art because they have art. Both arguments assume that if there is art in a given culture, then some members of the culture have a concept of art. There are reasons to think that this assumption is false; and if it is false, there are lessons to learn for cross-cultural studies of art both in anthropology and…Read more
  •  138
    Beauty, The Social Network
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 47 (4): 437-453. 2017.
    Aesthetic values give agents reasons to perform not only acts of contemplation, but also acts like editing, collecting, and conserving. Moreover, aesthetic agents rarely operate solo: they conduct their business as integral members of networks of other aesthetic agents. The consensus theory of aesthetic value, namely that an item’s aesthetic value is its power to evoke a finally valuable experience in a suitable spectator, can explain neither the range of acts performed by aesthetic agents nor t…Read more
  •  60
    Aesthetics of Interaction in Digital Art (review)
    British Journal of Aesthetics 55 (2): 261-263. 2015.
  •  120
    Drawing in a Social Science: Lithic Illustration
    Perspectives on Science 17 (1). 2009.
    Scientific images represent types or particulars. According to a standard history and epistemology of scientific images, drawings are fit to represent types and machine-made images are fit to represent particulars. The fact that archaeologists use drawings of particulars challenges this standard history and epistemology. It also suggests an account of the epistemic quality of archaeological drawings. This account stresses how images integrate non-conceptual and interepretive content.
  •  72
    A Philosophy of Mass Art (review)
    Philosophical Review 109 (4): 614. 2000.
    The chief sources of aesthetic experience for most people around the world are now the mass broadcasting and recording technologies. Yet analytic aesthetics has had little to say about mass art. Recent accounts of art and the aesthetic, while accommodating the consensus concerning central cases, are largely propelled by problem cases drawn from the avant-garde, and one wonders what the effect will be of adding works of mass art to the equation. One also wonders whether making room for mass art w…Read more
  •  1
    An Empathic Eye
    In Amy Coplan & Peter Goldie (eds.), Empathy. Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives, Oxford Univerity Press. pp. 118-133. 2011.
    What you see can shape how you feel, and the route from seeing to feeling sometimes involves empathy – as you might empathize with a woman you see grieving the death of her child. But empathy also comes from what you see in pictures. Bellini's Pieta? is one among many paintings, drawings, prints, and photographs that evoke empathy – and are designed to do so. Going further, it seems that episodes of empathy triggered by pictures can help build up a person's capacity for empathic response. Indeed…Read more
  •  9
    Conceptual Art Is Not What It Seems
    In Peter Goldie & Elisabeth Schellekens (eds.), Philosophy and conceptual art, Oxford University Press. 2007.
    Hypotheses in aesthetics should explain appreciative failure as well as appreciative success. They should state the general conditions under which people fail to understand and value works as works of art. This stricture is all the more important when the typical response to conceptual art is one of resistance. Some philosophers explain this by claiming that conceptual art violates traditional theories of art. Others say that it violates folk ontologies of art. In fact, the appreciative failure …Read more
  •  274
    Art Media and the Sense Modalities: Tactile Pictures
    Philosophical Quarterly 47 (189): 425-440. 1997.
    It is widely assumed that the art media can be individuated with reference to the sense modalities. Different art media are perceived by means of different sense modalities, and this tells us what properties of each medium are aesthetically relevant. The case of pictures appears to fit this principle well, for pictures are deemed purely and paradigmatically visual representations. However, recent psychological studies show that congenitally and early blind people have the ability to interpret an…Read more
  •  58
    From Languages of Art to Art in Mind
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 58 (3): 227-231. 2000.
  • Ahora todos somos artistas
    Enrahonar: Quaderns de Filosofía 50 45-57. 2013.
  •  190
    The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics (edited book)
    with Berys Nigel Gaut
    Routledge. 2000.
    The third edition of the acclaimed _Routledge Companion to Aesthetics_ contains over sixty chapters written by leading international scholars covering all aspects of aesthetics. This companion opens with an historical overview of aesthetics including entries on Plato, Aristotle, Kant, Nietzsche, Heidegger, Adorno, Benjamin, Foucault, Goodman, and Wollheim. The second part covers the central concepts and theories of aesthetics, including the definitions of art, taste, the value of art, beauty, im…Read more
  • Afterword
    In Dominic Lopes (ed.), Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures, Oxford University Press. 2005.
  •  82
    This authoritative volume offers a handy compilation of contributions to the field by its leading figures.
  •  6
    Genre
    with Brian Laetz
    In Paisley Livingston & Carl Plantinga (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy and Film, Routledge. pp. 152-161. 2008.
  •  197
    Hearing and Seeing Musical Expression
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 78 (1): 1-16. 2008.
    Everybody assumes (1) that musical performances are sonic events and (2) that their expressive properties are sonic properties. This paper discusses recent findings in the psychology of music perception that show that visual information combines with auditory information in the perception of musical expression. The findings show at the very least that arguments are needed for (1) and (2). If music expresses what we think it does, then its expressive properties may be visual as well as sonic; and…Read more
  •  388
    Imagination, Philosophy and the Arts (edited book)
    Routledge. 2003.
    _Imagination, Philosophy and the Arts_ is the first comprehensive collection of papers by philosophers examining the nature of imagination and its role in understanding and making art. Imagination is a central concept in aesthetics with close ties to issues in the philosophy of mind and the philosophy of language, yet it has not received the kind of sustained, critical attention it deserves. This collection of seventeen brand new essays critically examines just how and in what form the notion of…Read more
  • The third edition of the acclaimed Routledge Companion to Aesthetics contains over sixty chapters written by leading international scholars covering all aspects of aesthetics. This companion opens with an historical overview of aesthetics including entries on Plato, Aristotle, Kant, Nietzsche, Heidegger, Adorno, Benjamin, Foucault, Goodman, and Wollheim. The second part covers the central concepts and theories of aesthetics, including the definitions of art, taste, the value of art, beauty, imag…Read more
  • Imagination, Philosophy, and the Arts
    with Matthew Kieran
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 63 (1): 86-89. 2005.
  •  172
    The Ontology of Interactive Art
    Journal of Aesthetic Education 35 (4): 65-81. 2001.
  •  81
    Objects of Appropriation
    with Andrea Naomi Walsh
    In James O. Young & Conrad G. Brunk (eds.), The Ethics of Cultural Appropriation, Wiley. 2009.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Introduction Monument as Museum, Museum as Monument Arts of Appropriation Appropriation, Property and Oppression Appropriation, Memory and Identity References.