•  49
    Perl and Schroeder’s presuppositional error theory
    Philosophical Studies 176 (6): 1473-1493. 2019.
    Ronald Dworkin charges that the error theory is a position in first-order moral theory that should be judged by the standards that are appropriately used in evaluating first-order theories. Perl and Schroeder contend that a “presuppositional error theory” can avoid Dworkin’s charge. On the presuppositional view, moral sentences, such as, “It is wrong to torture babies,” have a false presupposition. Perhaps, for example, they presuppose that there are objectively prescriptive moral standards. Thi…Read more
  •  94
    The fundamental issue dividing normative naturalists and non-naturalists concerns the nature of normativity. Non-naturalists hold that the normativity of moral properties and facts sets them apart from natural properties and facts in an important and deep way. As Derek Parfit explains matters, the normative naturalist distinguishes between normative concepts and the natural properties to which these concepts refer and also between normative propositions and the natural facts in virtue of which s…Read more
  •  170
    Evolutionary debunking arguments aim to undercut the epistemological status of our evaluative beliefs on the basis of the genesis of our belief-forming tendencies. This paper addresses the issue whether responses to these arguments must be question-begging. It argues for a pragmatic understanding of question-beggingness, according to which whether an argument is question-begging depends on the argumentative context. After laying out the debunking argument, the paper considers a variety of respon…Read more
  •  155
    Just too different: normative properties and natural properties
    Philosophical Studies 177 (1): 263-286. 2020.
    Many normative nonnaturalists find normative naturalism to be completely implausible. Naturalists and nonnaturalists agree, provided they are realists, that there are normative properties, such as moral ones. Naturalists hold that these properties are similar in all metaphysically important respects to properties that all would agree to be natural ones, such as such as meteorological or economic ones. It is this view that the nonnaturalists I have in mind find to be hopeless. They hold that norm…Read more
  •  99
    A semantic challenge to non-realist cognitivism
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 48 (3-4): 569-591. 2018.
    Recently, some philosophers have attempted to escape familiar challenges to orthodox nonnaturalist normative realism by abandoning the robust metaphysical commitments of the orthodox view. One such view is the ‘Non-Metaphysical Non-Naturalism’ or ‘Non-Realist Cognitivism’ proposed by Derek Parfit and a few others. The trouble is that, as it stands, Non-Realist Cognitivism seems unable to provide a substantive non-trivial account of the meaning and truth conditions of moral claims. The paper cons…Read more
  •  60
    Pejoratives and Ways of Thinking
    Analytic Philosophy 58 (3): 248-271. 2017.
  •  77
    Realist-expressivism and the fundamental role of normative belief
    Philosophical Studies 175 (6): 1333-1356. 2018.
    The goal of this paper is to show that a cognitivist–externalist view about moral judgment is compatible with a key intuition that motivates non-cognitivist expressivism. This is the intuition that normative judgments have a close connection to action that ordinary “descriptive factual beliefs” do not have, or, as James Dreier has suggested, that part of the fundamental role of normative judgment is to motivate. One might think that cognitivist–externalist positions about normative judgment are …Read more
  •  5
    Pluralism and Stability in Liberal Theory
    Journal of Political Philosophy 4 (3): 191-206. 1996.
  •  18
    3. Capitalism versus Democracy: The Marketing of Votes and the Marketing of Political Power
    In John Douglas Bishop (ed.), Ethics and Capitalism, University of Toronto Press. pp. 81-101. 2000.
  •  14
  •  5
    The Iterated-Utilitarianism of J.S. Mill
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 5 (n/a): 75-98. 1979.
    The interpretation of the utilitarianism of John Stuart Mill has been a matter of controversy at least since J.O. Urmson published his well known paper over twenty-five years ago. Urmson attributed to Mill a form of “rule-utilitarianism”, contrasting his reading with the “received view” on which Mill held a form of “act-utilitarianism”. Since then, the interpretive problem has typically been seen to be that of determining which of these two types of theory should be attributed to Mill, or, at le…Read more
  •  6
    Moral reasons
    Philosophical Books 35 (3): 197-199. 1994.
  •  29
    Wanting the bad and doing bad things: an essay in moral psychology
    with Peter Brian Barry, Anton Tupa, Marina Oshana, Crystal Thorpe, and Dolores Albarracin
    Title from title page of source document
  • International justice and the basic needs principle
    In Gillian Brock & Harry Brighouse (eds.), Protosociology, Cambridge University Press. pp. 39--54. 2005.
    According to the basic needs principle, a state in favorable circumstances must enable its members to meet their basic needs throughout a normal life-span. Applied to the international situation, I argue, this principle implies that a global state would have a duty to enable subordinate states to meet their members‘ needs. In the absence of a global state, existing states have a duty to work to create a system of institutions that would enable each state to meet its members‘ needs. Near the conc…Read more
  •  83
    The Concept of a Society
    Dialogue 31 (2): 183-. 1992.
    The concept of a society is central to several areas of philosophy, including social and political philosophy, philosophy of social science and moral philosophy. Yet little attention has been paid to the concept and we do not have an adequate philosophical account of it. It is a concept that is difficult to explain systematically, and it is subject to distortion or simple-minded attacks whenever it plays a major role in a philosophical theory. Methodological individualists have raised metaphysic…Read more
  •  866
    The wrong answer to an improper question?
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 33. 2010.
    A philosopher who asks “Why be moral?” is asking a theoretical question about the force of moral reasons or about the normative status of morality. Two questions need to be distinguished. First, assuming that there is a morally preferred way to live or to be, is there any (further) reason to be this way or to act this way? Second, if moral considerations are a source of reasons, why is this, and what is the significance of these reasons? This question asks for a ‘grounding’ of morality. The p…Read more
  •  35
    The Problem Economic efficiency is naturally thought to be a virtue of social policies and decisions, and cost-benefit analysis is commonly regarded as a technique for measuring economic efficiency. It is not surprising, then, that CB analysis is so widely used in social policy analysis. However, there is a great deal of controversy about CB analysis, including controversy about its underlying philosophical rationale. The rationales that have been proposed fall into three basic, though not mutua…Read more
  •  2
    The Idea of Democracy
    with Jean Hampton and John E. Roemer
    Ethics 105 (2): 425-426. 1995.
    In the wake of the recent expansion of democratic forms of government around the world, political theorists have begun to rethink the nature and justification of this form of government. The essays in this book address a variety of foundational questions about democracy: How effective is it? How stable can it be in a pluralist society? Does it deserve its current popularity? Can it successfully guide a socialist society?
  •  33
    Goldman on the goals of democracy (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (1). 2002.
    As practiced by Alvin Goldman, social epistemology addresses the epistemic consequences and requirements of social practices and institutions. Since political institutions have epistemic consequences and requirements, social epistemology has a great deal to offer to political philosophy. Goldman’s work in this area is rich and interesting, and, in his recent book, Knowledge in a Social World, he has much to say that deserves the attention of political philosophers. I highly recommend, for exampl…Read more
  •  18
    Morals By Agreement (review)
    Philosophical Review 98 (3): 411-414. 1989.
  •  466
    According to the principle of alternate possibilities (PAP), a person is morally responsible for an action only if he could have done otherwise. PAP underlies a familiar argument for the incompatibility of moral responsibility with determinism. I argue that Harry Frankfurt's famous argument against PAP is unsuccessful if PAP is interpreted as a principle about blameworthiness. My argument turns on the maxim that "ought implies can" as well as a "finely-nuanced" view of the object of blame. To re…Read more
  •  65