•  35
    The Problem Economic efficiency is naturally thought to be a virtue of social policies and decisions, and cost-benefit analysis is commonly regarded as a technique for measuring economic efficiency. It is not surprising, then, that CB analysis is so widely used in social policy analysis. However, there is a great deal of controversy about CB analysis, including controversy about its underlying philosophical rationale. The rationales that have been proposed fall into three basic, though not mutua…Read more
  •  2
    The Idea of Democracy
    with Jean Hampton and John E. Roemer
    Ethics 105 (2): 425-426. 1995.
    In the wake of the recent expansion of democratic forms of government around the world, political theorists have begun to rethink the nature and justification of this form of government. The essays in this book address a variety of foundational questions about democracy: How effective is it? How stable can it be in a pluralist society? Does it deserve its current popularity? Can it successfully guide a socialist society?
  •  33
    Goldman on the goals of democracy (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (1). 2002.
    As practiced by Alvin Goldman, social epistemology addresses the epistemic consequences and requirements of social practices and institutions. Since political institutions have epistemic consequences and requirements, social epistemology has a great deal to offer to political philosophy. Goldman’s work in this area is rich and interesting, and, in his recent book, Knowledge in a Social World, he has much to say that deserves the attention of political philosophers. I highly recommend, for exampl…Read more
  •  18
    Morals By Agreement (review)
    Philosophical Review 98 (3): 411-414. 1989.
  •  466
    According to the principle of alternate possibilities (PAP), a person is morally responsible for an action only if he could have done otherwise. PAP underlies a familiar argument for the incompatibility of moral responsibility with determinism. I argue that Harry Frankfurt's famous argument against PAP is unsuccessful if PAP is interpreted as a principle about blameworthiness. My argument turns on the maxim that "ought implies can" as well as a "finely-nuanced" view of the object of blame. To re…Read more
  •  39
    Article 25 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights reads as follows: “Everyone has the right to a standard of living adequate for the health and well-being of himself and of his family, including food, clothing, housing and medical care and necessary social services.” I shall refer to the right postulated here as “the right to an adequate standard of living” or “The Right.”
  •  65
  •  2
    Morality, Normativity, and Society
    Philosophical Quarterly 47 (188): 411-413. 1997.
  •  138
    The normativity of self-grounded reason
    Social Philosophy and Policy 22 (2): 165-203. 2005.
    In this essay, I propose a standard of practical rationality and a grounding for the standard that rests on the idea of autonomous agency. This grounding is intended to explain the “normativity” of the standard. The basic idea is this: To be autonomous is to be self-governing. To be rational is at least in part to be self-governing; it is to do well in governing oneself. I argue that a person's values are aspects of her identity—of her “self-esteem identity”—in a way that most of her ends are no…Read more
  •  27
    International Justice and the Basic Needs Principle
    ProtoSociology 26 150-166. 2009.
    According to the basic needs principle, a state in favorable circumstances must enable its members to meet their basic needs throughout a normal life-span. Applied to the international situation, I argue, this principle implies that a global state would have a duty (ceteris paribus) to enable subordinate states to meet their members‘ needs. In the absence of a global state, existing states have a duty (ceteris paribus) to work to create a system of institutions that would enable each state to me…Read more
  •  307
    Toward a pluralist and teleological theory of normativity
    Philosophical Issues 19 (1): 21-37. 2009.
    No Abstract
  •  558
    Realist-Expressivism: A Neglected Option for Moral Realism
    Social Philosophy and Policy 18 (2): 1-43. 2001.
    Moral realism and antirealist-expressivism are of course incompatible positions. They disagree fundamentally about the nature of moral states of mind, the existence of moral states of affairs and properties, and the nature and role of moral discourse. The central realist view is that a person who has or expresses a moral thought is thereby in, or thereby expresses, a cognitive state of mind; she has or expresses a belief that represents a moral state of affairs in a way that might be accurate or…Read more
  •  124
    (2000). Four Epistemological Challenges to Ethical Naturalism: Naturalized Epistemology and the First-Person Perspective. Canadian Journal of Philosophy: Vol. 30, Supplementary Volume 26: Moral Epistemology Naturalized, pp. 30-74.
  •  16
    Reasons and Societies
    Philosophical Quarterly 48 (190): 96-102. 1998.
  •  194
    An account of the ontological nature of collectives would be useful for several reasons. A successful theory would help to show us a route through the thicket of views known as “methodological individualism”. It would have a bearing on the plausibility of legal positivism. It would be relevant to the question whether collectives are capable of acting. The debate about the ontology of collectives is therefore important for such fields as the theory of action, social and political philosophy, the …Read more
  •  4
    This paper is a reply to Anton Leist’s criticisms of the view I develop in my book, Morality, Normativity, and Society. Leist claims that my “standard-based” account of the truth conditions of moral propositions is incoherent. I argue that he is mistaken about this. Leist claims that my “society-centered” account of the justification of moral standards has “nasty” implications. In the course of answering this worry, I develop the idea of a “moral necessity”. My theory implies that although moral…Read more
  •  304
    The Ring of Gyges: Overridingness and the Unity of Reason
    Social Philosophy and Policy 14 (1): 86-106. 1997.
    Does morality override self-interest? Or does self-interest override morality? These questions become important in situations where there is conflict between the overall verdicts of morality and self-interest, situations where morality on balance requires an action that is contrary to our self-interest, or where considerations of self-interest on balance call for an action that is forbidden by morality. In situations of this kind, we want to know what we ought simpliciter to do. If one of these …Read more
  •  52
    Michael H. Robins, 1941-2002
    with Michael Bradie and Christopher Morris
    Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 76 (5). 2003.
    This is an obituary for Michael H. Robins.
  •  13
    Morality, Reason, and Management Science: The Rationale of Cost-Benefit Analysis
    Social Philosophy and Policy 2 (2): 128-151. 1985.
    The ProblemEconomic efficiency is naturally thought to be a virtue of social policies and decisions, and cost-benefit (CB) analysis is commonly regarded as a technique for measuring economic efficiency. It is not surprising, then, that CB analysis is so widely used in social policy analysis. However, there is a great deal of controversy about CB analysis, including controversy about its underlying philosophical rationale. The rationales that have been proposed fall into three basic, though not m…Read more
  •  242
    The Idea of a Legitimate State
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 28 (1): 3-45. 1999.
    A legitimate state would have a right to rule. The problem is to understand, first, precisely what this right amounts to, and second, under what conditions a state would have it. According to the traditional account, the legitimacy of a state is to be explained in terms of its subjects’ obligation to obey the law. I argue that this account is inadequate. I propose that the legitimacy of a state would consist in its having a bundle of rights of various kinds, which I specify. Among other thi…Read more
  •  9
    Goldman on the Goals of Democracy
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (1): 207-214. 2002.
    As practiced by Alvin Goldman, social epistemology addresses the epistemic consequences and requirements of social practices and institutions. Since political institutions have epistemic consequences and requirements, social epistemology has a great deal to offer to political philosophy. Goldman’s work in this area is rich and interesting, and, in his recent book, Knowledge in a Social World, he has much to say that deserves the attention of political philosophers. I highly recommend, for exampl…Read more
  •  25
    Review of Moral Reasons (review)
    Philosophical Books 35 (3): 197-199. 1994.
  •  219
    Do we have any justified moral beliefs? (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77 (3): 811-819. 2008.
    No Abstract