•  1
    From Logic through Ontology to Phenomenology
    In Jorge J. E. Gracia, Gregory M. Reichberg & Bernard N. Schumacher (eds.), The Classics of Western Philosophy: A Reader's Guide, Wiley-blackwell. 2003.
  •  72
    Philosophy and the mirror of nature
    Philosophical Topics 12 (2): 288-294. 1981.
  •  79
    Mind World: Essays in Phenomenology and Ontology
    Cambridge University Press. 2004.
    This collection explores the structure of consciousness and its place in the world, or inversely the structure of the world and the place of consciousness in it. Amongst the topics covered are: the phenomenological aspects of experience, dependencies between experience and the world and the basic ontological categories found in the world at large. Developing ideas drawn from historical figures such as Descartes, Husserl, Aristotle, and Whitehead, the essays together demonstrate the interdependen…Read more
  •  111
    Is this a dagger I see before me?
    Synthese 54 (January): 95-114. 1983.
  •  49
    The Several Factors of Consciousness
    Rivista Internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia 7 (3): 291-302. 2016.
    : In prior essays I have sketched a “modal model” of consciousness. That model “factors” out several distinct forms of awareness in the phenomenological structure of a typical act of consciousness. Here we consider implications of the model à propos of contemporary theories of consciousness. In particular, we distinguish phenomenality from other features of awareness in a conscious experience: “what it is like” to have an experience involves several different factors. Further, we should see thes…Read more
  •  176
    How to Husserl a Quine — and a Heidegger, too
    Synthese 98 (1): 153-173. 1994.
    Is consciousness or the subject part of the natural world or the human world? Can we write intentionality, so central in Husserl's philosophy, into Quine's system of ontological naturalism and naturalized epistemology — or into Heidegger's account of human being and existential phenomenology? The present task is to show how to do so. Anomalous monism provides a key.
  •  70
    The cogito circa ad 2000
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 36 (3). 1993.
    What are we to make of the cogito (cogito ergo sum) today, as the walls of Cartesian philosophy crumble around us? The enduring foundation of the cogito is consciousness. It is in virtue of a particular phenomenological structure that an experience is conscious rather than unconscious. Drawing on an analysis of that structure, the cogito is given a new explication that synthesizes phenomenological, epistemological, logical, and ontological elements. What, then, is the structure of conscious thin…Read more
  •  50
    “Pure” logic, ontology, and phenomenology
    Revue Internationale de Philosophie 224 (2): 21-44. 2003.
  •  120
    Consciousness in action
    Synthese 90 (1): 119-43. 1992.
    A phenomenology of action is outlined, analyzing the structure of volition, kinesthesis, and perception in the experience of action, and, finally, the experience of embodiment in action. The intentionality of action is contrasted with that of thought and perception in regard to the role of the body, and the relations between an action, the experience of acting, and the context of the action are specified
  •  105
    Ontological Phenomenology
    The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 7 243-251. 2000.
    Phenomenology is the study of conscious experience from the first-person point of view. Husserl used principles of formal ontology even as he bracketed the natural-cultural world in describing our experience, and Heidegger pursued fundamental ontology in his variety of phenomenology describing our own modes of existence. I shall address the role of ontology in phenomenology, and vice versa. Our account of what exists depends on our account of what and how we experience. But, moreover, our unders…Read more
  •  122
    Mathematical form in the world
    Philosophia Mathematica 10 (2): 102-129. 2002.
    This essay explores an ideal notion of form (mathematical structure) that embraces logical, phenomenological, and ontological form. Husserl envisioned a correlation among forms of expression, thought, meaning, and object—positing ideal forms on all these levels. The most puzzling formal entities Husserl discussed were those he called ‘manifolds’. These manifolds, I propose, are forms of complex states of affairs or partial possible worlds representable by forms of theories (compare structuralism…Read more
  •  68
    The ins and outs of perception
    Philosophical Studies 49 (March): 187-211. 1986.
  •  24
    Husserl and Frege
    Philosophical Review 95 (1): 118. 1986.
  •  66
    The body, merleau-ponty claimed, carries a unique form of intentionality that is not reducible to the intentionality of thought. i propose to separate several different forms of intentionality concerning such ``bodily intentionality'': awareness of one's body and bodily movement; purposive action; and perception of one's environment in acting. these different forms of awareness are interdependent in specific ways. no one form of intentionality--cognitive or practical--is an absolute foundation f…Read more
  •  8
    Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (review)
    Philosophical Topics 12 (2): 288-294. 1981.
  • Mind World: Essays in Phenomenology and Ontology
    Philosophical Quarterly 56 (224): 457-459. 2006.
  •  81
    Kantifying in
    Synthese 54 (2). 1983.
  •  273
    What's the meaning of 'this'?
    Noûs 16 (2): 181-208. 1982.
    "This is a sea urchin", I declare while strolling the beach with a friend. What do I refer to by uttering the demonstrative pronoun "this"? The object immediately before me, of course. As it happens on this occasion, the object in the sand at my feet. I may point at it to aid my hearer - or I may not. BUt now , if the meaning of the term is distinguished from the referent, what is the meaning of this, or of my utterance of this? I think we can distinguish the meaning of this, or of its utterance…Read more
  •  41
    Introduction
    with Andrea Bonomi
    Topoi 5 (2): 89-90. 1986.
  •  12
    Réponses à mes critiques
    Philosophiques 36 (2): 619-645. 2009.
  •  303
    Phenomenology
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
    Phenomenology is the study of structures of consciousness as experienced from the first-person point of view. The central structure of an experience is its intentionality, its being directed toward something, as it is an experience of or about some object. An experience is directed toward an object by virtue of its content or meaning (which represents the object) together with appropriate enabling conditions
  •  17