•  4
    Is Neuroscience Relevant to Philosophy?
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 16 (n/a): 323-341. 1990.
    Many questions concerning the nature of the mind have remained intractable since their first systematic discussion by the ancient Greeks. What is the nature of knowledge, and how is it possible to represent the world? What are consciousness and free will? What is the self and how is it that some organisms are more intelligent than others? Since it is now overwhelmingly evident that these are phenomena of the physical brain, it is not surprising that an established empirical and theoretical found…Read more
  •  677
    The hornswoggle problem
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 3 (5-6): 402-8. 1996.
    Beginning with Thomas Nagel, various philosophers have propsed setting conscious experience apart from all other problems of the mind as ‘the most difficult problem’. When critically examined, the basis for this proposal reveals itself to be unconvincing and counter-productive. Use of our current ignorance as a premise to determine what we can never discover is one common logical flaw. Use of ‘I-cannot-imagine’ arguments is a related flaw. When not much is known about a domain of phenomena, our …Read more
  •  107
  •  42
    Consciousness: The transmutation of a concept
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 64 (January): 80-95. 1983.
  •  90
    Explaining the nature and mechanisms of conscious experience in neurobiological terms seems to be an attainable, if yet unattained, goal. Research at many levels is important, including research at the cellular level that explores the role of recurrent pathways between thalamic nuclei and the cortex, and research that explores consciousness from the perspective of action. Conceptually, a clearer understanding of the logic of expressions such as ‘‘causes’’ and ‘‘correlates’’, and about what to ex…Read more
  •  391
    This is a unique book. It is excellently written, crammed with information, wise and a pleasure to read.' ---Daniel C. Dennett, Tufts University
  •  2
    Filling in
    with Why Dennett is Wrong and Vilayanur S. Ramachandran
    In Antti Revonsuo & Matti Kamppinen (eds.), Consciousness in Philosophy and Cognitive Neuroscience, Lawrence Erlbaum. 1994.
  •  27
    Leapfrog over the brain
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (1): 73-74. 1987.
  •  181
    The timing of sensations: Reply to Libet
    Philosophy of Science 48 (3): 492-7. 1981.
  •  225
    Is determinism self-refuting?
    Mind 90 (January): 99-101. 1981.
  •  152
    Epistemology in the Age of Neuroscience
    Journal of Philosophy 84 (10): 544-553. 1987.
  •  216
    The neural mechanisms of moral cognition: A multiple-aspect approach to moral judgment and decision-making (review)
    with William D. Casebeer
    Biology and Philosophy 18 (1): 169-194. 2003.
    We critically review themushrooming literature addressing the neuralmechanisms of moral cognition (NMMC), reachingthe following broad conclusions: (1) researchmainly focuses on three inter-relatedcategories: the moral emotions, moral socialcognition, and abstract moral reasoning. (2)Research varies in terms of whether it deploysecologically valid or experimentallysimplified conceptions of moral cognition. Themore ecologically valid the experimentalregime, the broader the brain areas involved.(3)…Read more
  •  31
    4 The View from Here: The Nonsymbolic Structure of Spatial
    with Ilya Farber and Will Peterman
    In João Branquinho (ed.), The Foundations of Cognitive Science, Oxford University Press Uk. 2001.
  •  45
    Internal states and cognitive theories
    with Paul M. Churchland
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1 (4): 565-566. 1978.
  •  222
    Philosophy, in its traditional guise, addresses questions where experimental science has not yet nailed down plausible explanatory theories. Thus, the ancient Greeks pondered the nature of life, the sun, and tides, but also how we learn and make decisions. The history of science can be seen as a gradual process whereby speculative philosophy cedes intellectual space to increasingly wellgrounded experimental disciplines—first astronomy, but followed by physics, chemistry, geology, biology, archae…Read more
  •  218
    Progress in the neurosciences is profoundly changing our conception of ourselves. Contrary to time-honored intuition, the mind turns out to be a complex of brain functions. And contrary to the wishful thinking of some philosophers, there is no stemming the revolutionary impact that brain research will have on our understanding of how the mind works. Brain-Wise is the sequel to Patricia Smith Churchland's Neurophilosophy, the book that launched a subfield. In a clear, conversational manner, this …Read more
  •  90
    Neural worlds and real worlds
    with Paul M. Churchland
    Nature Reviews Neuroscience 3. 2002.
    States of the brain represent states of the world. A puzzle arises when one learns that at least some of the mind/brain’s internal representations, such as a sensation of heat or a sensation of red, do not genuinely resemble the external realities they allegedly represent: the mean kinetic energy of the molecules of the substance felt (temperature) and the mean electromagnetic reflectance profile of the seen object (color). The historical response has been to declare a distinction between object…Read more
  •  80
    “Neuroscience is Relevant for Philosophy”
    Problemos (88): 176-186. 2015.
    This is an interview with Professor Patricia S. Churchland. It covers themes such as eliminative materialism, folk psychology, neurophilosophy, the relationship between philosophy and science, moral norms as well as the criticism of contemporary analytic philosophy.
  •  23
    Introduction: Neurophilosophy and Alzheimer's Disease
    In Y. Christen & P.S. Churchland (eds.), Neurophilosophy and Alzheimer's Disease, Springer Verlag. pp. 1--4. 1992.