Columbia University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1989
San Diego, California, United States of America
  •  129
    Knowledge requires both freedom and friction . Freedom to set up our epistemic goals, choose the subject matter of our investigations, espouse cognitive norms, design research programs, etc., and friction (constraint) coming from two directions: the object or target of our investigation, i.e., the world in a broad sense, and our mind as the sum total of constraints involving the knower. My goal is to investigate the problem of epistemic friction, the relation between epistemic friction and freed…Read more
  •  121
    In Search of a Substantive Theory of Truth
    Journal of Philosophy 101 (1): 5-36. 2004.
  •  120
    Truth, Logical Structure, and Compositionality
    Synthese 126 (1-2): 195-219. 2001.
    In this paper I examine a cluster of concepts relevant to the methodology of truth theories: 'informative definition', 'recursive method', 'semantic structure', 'logical form', 'compositionality', etc. The interrelations between these concepts, I will try to show, are more intricate and multi-dimensional than commonly assumed.
  •  116
    Where are You Going, Philosophy, and What are Your Methods?
    Academics Journal 271 185-96. 2020.
    The viability of philosophy as a genuine field of knowledge has been challenged time and again. Some have challenged “traditional” philosophy, or what was considered “traditional philosophy” at a given time; others have challenged philosophy in general. But there has been considerable progress in philosophical methodology in the 20th- and 21st- centuries. In this talk I raise challenges to some of the current misconceptions of analytic philosophy, and I propose constructive methodological soluti…Read more
  •  116
    Did Tarski commit "Tarski's fallacy"?
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (2): 653-686. 1996.
    In his 1936 paper,On the Concept of Logical Consequence, Tarski introduced the celebrated definition oflogical consequence: “The sentenceσfollows logicallyfrom the sentences of the class Γ if and only if every model of the class Γ is also a model of the sentenceσ.” [55, p. 417] This definition, Tarski said, is based on two very basic intuitions, “essential for the proper concept of consequence” [55, p. 415] and reflecting common linguistic usage: “Consider any class Γ of sentences and a sentence…Read more
  •  110
    What is Tarski's Theory of Truth?
    Topoi 18 (2): 149-166. 1999.
  •  109
    Ways of branching quantifers
    Linguistics and Philosophy 13 (4). 1990.
    Branching quantifiers were first introduced by L. Henkin in his 1959 paper ‘Some Remarks on Infmitely Long Formulas’. By ‘branching quantifiers’ Henkin meant a new, non-linearly structured quantiiier-prefix whose discovery was triggered by the problem of interpreting infinitistic formulas of a certain form} The branching (or partially-ordered) quantifier-prefix is, however, not essentially infinitistic, and the issues it raises have largely been discussed in the literature in the context of fini…Read more
  •  109
    Between logic and intuition: essays in honor of Charles Parsons (edited book)
    with Richard Tieszen
    Cambridge University Press. 2000.
    This collection of new essays offers a 'state-of-the-art' conspectus of major trends in the philosophy of logic and philosophy of mathematics. A distinguished group of philosophers addresses issues at the centre of contemporary debate: semantic and set-theoretic paradoxes, the set/class distinction, foundations of set theory, mathematical intuition and many others. The volume includes Hilary Putnam's 1995 Alfred Tarski lectures, published here for the first time.
  •  109
    The foundational problem of logic
    Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 19 (2): 145-198. 2013.
    The construction of a systematic philosophical foundation for logic is a notoriously difficult problem. In Part One I suggest that the problem is in large part methodological, having to do with the common philosophical conception of “providing a foundation”. I offer an alternative to the common methodology which combines a strong foundational requirement with the use of non-traditional, holistic tools to achieve this result. In Part Two I delineate an outline of a foundation for logic, employing…Read more
  •  104
    Tarski's thesis
    In Douglas Patterson (ed.), New Essays on Tarski and Philosophy, Oxford University Press. pp. 300--339. 2008.
  •  92
    Partially-ordered (branching) generalized quantifiers: A general definition
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 26 (1): 1-43. 1997.
    Following Henkin's discovery of partially-ordered (branching) quantification (POQ) with standard quantifiers in 1959, philosophers of language have attempted to extend his definition to POQ with generalized quantifiers. In this paper I propose a general definition of POQ with 1-place generalized quantifiers of the simplest kind: namely, predicative, or "cardinality" quantifiers, e.g., "most", "few", "finitely many", "exactly α", where α is any cardinal, etc. The definition is obtained in a serie…Read more
  •  77
    A conception of Tarskian logic
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 70 (4): 341-368. 1989.
    In this paper I develop a new conception of Tarskian logic based on Tarski’s intuitive characterization of logical consequence as formal and necessary in his 1936 paper. Special emphasis is placed on the role of logic in our system of knowledge, the origins of semantics, the semantic definition of logical consequence, and the role of logical and non-logical terms in a logical system. The paper offers a new definition of logical terms based on the question: what division of terms into logical and…Read more
  •  75
    Is There a Place for Philosophy in Quine’s Theory?
    Journal of Philosophy 96 (10): 491-524. 1999.
    In the early part of the 20th century the logical positivists launched a powerful attack on traditional philosophy, rejecting the very idea of philosophy as a substantive discipline and replacing it with a practical, conventionalist, meta-theoretical view of philosophy. The positivist critique was based on a series of dichotomies: the analytic vs. the synthetic, the external vs. the internal, the apriori vs. the empirical, the meta-theoretical vs. the object- theoretical, the conventional vs. th…Read more
  •  72
    Functional pluralism
    Philosophical Books 46 (4): 311-330. 2005.
    This is a critique of Michael P. Lynch’s functional pluralism with respect to truth. The paper is sympathetic to Lynch’s overall approach to truth, but is critical of (i) his platitudinous characterization of the general principles of truth, (ii) his excessive pluralism with respect to the “realizers” of truth, (iii) his treatment of atomic truth, and (iv) his analysis of “mixed” logical inferences. The paper concludes with a proposal for a functional pluralism that puts greater emphasis on the …Read more
  •  46
    Logical Consequence: An Epistemic Outlook
    The Monist 85 (4): 555-579. 2002.
    In this paper I present an outline of a model of knowledge that complements, and is complemented by, my the conception of logic delineated in The Bounds of Logic. The Bounds of Logic had as its goal a critical, systematic and constructive understanding of logic. As such it aimed at maximum neutrality vis-a-vis epistemic, metaphysical and meta-mathematical controversies. But a conception of logic does not exist in a vacuum. Eventually our goal is to produce an account of logic that answers the ne…Read more
  •  44
    Truth and Knowledge in Logic and Mathematics
    The Logica Yearbook 2011 289-304. 2012.
    Logic and mathematics are abstract disciplines par excellence. What is the nature of truth and knowledge in these disciplines? In this paper I investigate the possibility of a new approach to this question. The underlying idea is that knowledge qua knowledge, including logical and mathematical knowledge, has a dual grounding in mind and reality, and the standard of truth applicable to all knowledge is a correspondence standard. This applies to logic and mathematics as much as to other discipline…Read more
  •  36
  •  35
    Review of Robert Hanna, Rationality and Logic (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2007 (4): 1-6. 2007.
  •  29
    Logical Quantifiers
    In D. Graff Fara & G. Russell (eds.), Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Language, Routledge. pp. 579-595. 2012.
    This chapter offers a logical, linguistic, and philosophical account of modern quantification theory. Contrasting the standard approach to quantifiers (according to which logical quantifiers are defined by enumeration) with the generalized approach (according to which quantifiers are defined systematically), the chapter begins with a brief history of standard quantifier theory and identifies some of its logical, linguistic, and philosophical strengths and weaknesses. It then proceeds to a brief …Read more
  •  29
    In memoriam: Jaakko Hintikka
    Synthese 192 (8): 2337-2338. 2015.
  •  27
    A new defense of Tarski's solution to the liar paradox
    Philosophical Studies 180 (5-6): 1441-1466. 2022.
    Tarski's hierarchical solution to the Liar paradox is widely viewed as ad hoc. In this paper I show that, on the contrary, Tarski's solution is justified by a sound philosophical principle that concerns the inner structure of truth. This principle provides a common philosophical basis to a number of solutions to the Liar paradox, including Tarski's and Kripke's. Tarski himself may not have been aware of this principle, but by providing a philosophical basis to his hierarchical solution to the pa…Read more
  •  27
    A Characterization of Logical Constants Is Possible
    Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 18 (2): 189-198. 2010.
    ...
  •  26
    Did Tarski commit “Tarski's fallacy”?
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (2): 653-686. 1996.
    In his 1936 paper,On the Concept of Logical Consequence, Tarski introduced the celebrated definition oflogical consequence: “The sentenceσfollows logicallyfrom the sentences of the class Γ if and only if every model of the class Γ is also a model of the sentenceσ.” [55, p. 417] This definition, Tarski said, is based on two very basic intuitions, “essential for the proper concept of consequence” [55, p. 415] and reflecting common linguistic usage: “Consider any class Γ of sentences and a sentence…Read more
  •  25
    Book Review: Quantifiers in Language and Logic (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 107 (2): 103-112. 2010.
  •  19
    Book Review: Protocols, Truth and Convention (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 35 (1): 153-155. 1997.
    The continuing philosophical interest in the famous 'Protocol Sentence Debate' in the Vienna Circle of Logical Positivists is, to a large measure, due to the focus on the epistemological issues in the dispute, and the neglect of differences among the leading players in their philosophical views of logic and language. In Protocols, Truth and Convention , the current understanding of the debate is advanced by developing the contemporaneous views of logic and language held by the principal disputan…Read more
  •  18
    Is There a Place for Philosophy in Quine’s Theory?
    Journal of Philosophy 96 (10): 491-524. 1999.