Columbia University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1989
San Diego, California, United States of America
  • The Bounds of Logic: A Generalized Viewpoint
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (4): 1078-1083. 1991.
  •  429
    Truth and Scientific Change
    Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 48 (3): 371-394. 2017.
    The paper seeks to answer two new questions about truth and scientific change: What lessons does the phenomenon of scientific change teach us about the nature of truth? What light do recent developments in the theory of truth, incorporating these lessons, throw on problems arising from the prevalence of scientific change, specifically, the problem of pessimistic meta-induction?
  •  311
    Lessons on Truth from Kant
    Analytic Philosophy 58 (3): 171-201. 2017.
    Kant is known for having said relatively little about truth in Critique of Pure Reason. Nevertheless, there are important lessons to be learned from this work about truth, lessons that apply to the contemporary debate on the nature and structure of truth and its theory. In this paper I suggest two such lessons. The first lesson concerns the structure of a substantive theory of truth as contrasted with a deflationist theory; the second concerns the structure of a correspondence theory of truth. T…Read more
  •  14
    A Characterization of Logical Constants Is Possible
    Theoria 18 (2): 189-198. 2010.
    ...
  •  27
    A Characterization of Logical Constants Is Possible
    Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 18 (2): 189-198. 2010.
    ...
  •  8
    Review: D. M. Gabbay, What is a Logical System? (review)
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (4): 1396-1400. 1996.
  •  220
    Forms of correspondence: the intricate route from thought to reality
    In Nikolaj Jang Lee Linding Pedersen & Cory Wright (eds.), Truth and Pluralism: Current Debates, Oxford University Press. pp. 157--179. 2012.
    The paper delineates a new approach to truth that falls under the category of “Pluralism within the bounds of correspondence”, and illustrates it with respect to mathematical truth. Mathematical truth, like all other truths, is based on correspondence, but the route of mathematical correspondence differs from other routes of correspondence in (i) connecting mathematical truths to a special aspect of reality, namely, its formal aspect, and (ii) doing so in a complex, indirect way, rather than in …Read more
  •  180
    A characterization of logical constants is possible
    Theoria 18 (2): 189-198. 2003.
    The paper argues that a philosophically informative and mathematically precise characterization is possible by (i) describing a particular proposal for such a characterization, (ii) showing that certain criticisms of this proposal are incorrect, and (iii) discussing the general issue of what a characterization of logical constants aims at achieving
  • Semantics and Logic
    In Shalom Lappin (ed.), The handbook of contemporary semantic theory, Blackwell Reference. pp. 509-535. 1996.
  •  109
    The foundational problem of logic
    Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 19 (2): 145-198. 2013.
    The construction of a systematic philosophical foundation for logic is a notoriously difficult problem. In Part One I suggest that the problem is in large part methodological, having to do with the common philosophical conception of “providing a foundation”. I offer an alternative to the common methodology which combines a strong foundational requirement with the use of non-traditional, holistic tools to achieve this result. In Part Two I delineate an outline of a foundation for logic, employing…Read more
  •  19
    Book Review: Protocols, Truth and Convention (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 35 (1): 153-155. 1997.
    The continuing philosophical interest in the famous 'Protocol Sentence Debate' in the Vienna Circle of Logical Positivists is, to a large measure, due to the focus on the epistemological issues in the dispute, and the neglect of differences among the leading players in their philosophical views of logic and language. In Protocols, Truth and Convention , the current understanding of the debate is advanced by developing the contemporaneous views of logic and language held by the principal disputan…Read more
  •  29
    In memoriam: Jaakko Hintikka
    Synthese 192 (8): 2337-2338. 2015.
  •  116
    Did Tarski commit "Tarski's fallacy"?
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (2): 653-686. 1996.
    In his 1936 paper,On the Concept of Logical Consequence, Tarski introduced the celebrated definition oflogical consequence: “The sentenceσfollows logicallyfrom the sentences of the class Γ if and only if every model of the class Γ is also a model of the sentenceσ.” [55, p. 417] This definition, Tarski said, is based on two very basic intuitions, “essential for the proper concept of consequence” [55, p. 415] and reflecting common linguistic usage: “Consider any class Γ of sentences and a sentence…Read more
  • Truth, the Liar, and Tarski's Semantics
    In D. Jacquette (ed.), A Companion to Philosophical Logic, Blackwell. pp. 145-163. 2002.
  •  104
    Tarski's thesis
    In Douglas Patterson (ed.), New essays on Tarski and philosophy, Oxford University Press. pp. 300--339. 2008.
  •  46
    Logical Consequence: An Epistemic Outlook
    The Monist 85 (4): 555-579. 2002.
    In this paper I present an outline of a model of knowledge that complements, and is complemented by, my the conception of logic delineated in The Bounds of Logic. The Bounds of Logic had as its goal a critical, systematic and constructive understanding of logic. As such it aimed at maximum neutrality vis-a-vis epistemic, metaphysical and meta-mathematical controversies. But a conception of logic does not exist in a vacuum. Eventually our goal is to produce an account of logic that answers the ne…Read more
  •  743
    Truth as a normative modality of cognitive acts
    In Dirk Greimann & Geo Siegwart (eds.), Truth and Speech Acts: Studies in the Philosophy of Language, Routledge. pp. 280-306. 2007.
    Attention to the conversational role of alethic terms seems to dominate, and even sometimes exhaust, many contemporary analyses of the nature of truth. Yet, because truth plays a role in judgment and assertion regardless of whether alethic terms are expressly used, such analyses cannot be comprehensive or fully adequate. A more general analysis of the nature of truth is therefore required – one which continues to explain the significance of truth independently of the role alethic terms play in d…Read more
  • The question motivating my investigation is: Are the basic philosophical principles underlying the "core" system of contemporary logic exhausted by the standard version? In particular, is the accepted narrow construal of the notion "logical term" justified? ;As a point of comparison I refer to systems of 1st-order logic with generalized quantifiers developed by mathematicians and linguists . Based on an analysis of the Tarskian conception of the role of logic I show that the standard division of…Read more
  •  77
    A conception of Tarskian logic
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 70 (4): 341-368. 1989.
    In this paper I develop a new conception of Tarskian logic based on Tarski’s intuitive characterization of logical consequence as formal and necessary in his 1936 paper. Special emphasis is placed on the role of logic in our system of knowledge, the origins of semantics, the semantic definition of logical consequence, and the role of logical and non-logical terms in a logical system. The paper offers a new definition of logical terms based on the question: what division of terms into logical and…Read more
  •  615
    Substantivism about truth
    Philosophy Compass 11 (12): 818-828. 2016.
    Substantivism is a general philosophical methodology advocating a substantive approach to philosophical theorizing. In this article, I present an overview of this methodology with a special emphasis on the field of truth. I begin with a framework for understanding what is at stake in the substantivist–deflationist debate and describe the substantivist critique of deflationism. I then proceed to discuss contemporary substantivism as a positive methodology, present examples of recent substantivist…Read more
  •  159
    The formal-structural view of logical consequence
    Philosophical Review 110 (2): 241-261. 2001.
    In a recent paper, “The Concept of Logical Consequence,” W. H. Hanson criticizes a formal-structural characterization of logical consequence in Tarski and Sher. Hanson accepts many principles of the formal-structural view. Relating to Sher 1991 and 1996a, he says
  •  25
    Book Review: Quantifiers in Language and Logic (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 107 (2): 103-112. 2010.
  •  121
    In Search of a Substantive Theory of Truth
    Journal of Philosophy 101 (1): 5-36. 2004.
  •  338
    Gila Sher approaches knowledge from the perspective of the basic human epistemic situation—the situation of limited yet resourceful beings, living in a complex world and aspiring to know it in its full complexity. What principles should guide them? Two fundamental principles of knowledge are epistemic friction and freedom. Knowledge must be substantially constrained by the world (friction), but without active participation of the knower in accessing the world (freedom) theoretical knowledge is i…Read more
  •  610
    Wallace, Free Choice, and Fatalism
    In Steven M. Cahn & Maureen Eckert (eds.), Freedom and the Self: Essays on the Philosophy of David Foster Wallace, Columbia University Press. pp. 31-56. 2015.
    In this paper I reconstruct David Foster Wallace’s argument against fatalism in his undergraduate honors thesis, “Richard Taylor’s ‘Fatalism’ and the Semantics of Physical Modality”. My goal is to present the argument in a clear and concise way, so that it is easy to see its main line of reasoning and potential power. A secondary goal is to offer clarificatory and critical notes on some of the issues at stake. The reconstruction reveals interesting connections between Wallace’s argument and John…Read more
  •  109
    Ways of branching quantifers
    Linguistics and Philosophy 13 (4). 1990.
    Branching quantifiers were first introduced by L. Henkin in his 1959 paper ‘Some Remarks on Infmitely Long Formulas’. By ‘branching quantifiers’ Henkin meant a new, non-linearly structured quantiiier-prefix whose discovery was triggered by the problem of interpreting infinitistic formulas of a certain form} The branching (or partially-ordered) quantifier-prefix is, however, not essentially infinitistic, and the issues it raises have largely been discussed in the literature in the context of fini…Read more
  •  29
    Logical Quantifiers
    In D. Graff Fara & G. Russell (eds.), Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Language, Routledge. pp. 579-595. 2012.
    This chapter offers a logical, linguistic, and philosophical account of modern quantification theory. Contrasting the standard approach to quantifiers (according to which logical quantifiers are defined by enumeration) with the generalized approach (according to which quantifiers are defined systematically), the chapter begins with a brief history of standard quantifier theory and identifies some of its logical, linguistic, and philosophical strengths and weaknesses. It then proceeds to a brief …Read more