•  308
    The poverty of the Popperian program for truthlikeness
    Philosophy of Science 53 (2): 163-178. 1986.
    The importance for realism of the concept of truthlikeness was first stressed by Popper. Popper himself not only mapped out a program for defining truthlikeness (in terms of falsity content and truth content) but produced the first definitions within this program. These were shown to be inadequate. But the program lingered on, and the most recent attempt to revive it is that of Newton-Smith. His attempt is a failure, not because of some minor defect or technical flaw in his particular account bu…Read more
  •  559
    Thinking Globally, Acting Locally: Partiality, Preferences and Perspective
    Les ateliers de l'éthique/The Ethics Forum 9 (2): 57-81. 2014.
    A rather promising value theory for environmental philosophers combines the well-known fitting attitude (FA) account of value with the rather less well-known account of value as richness. If the value of an entity is proportional to its degree of richness (which has been cashed out in terms of unified complexity and organic unity), then since natural entities, such as species or ecosystems, exhibit varying degrees of richness quite independently of what we happen to feel about them, they also po…Read more
  •  62
    Resplicing properties in the supervenience base
    with Pavel Tichý
    Philosophical Studies 58 (3): 259-69. 1990.
  •  155
  • Partial Interpretation, Meaning Variance, and Incommensurability
    In Kostas Gavroglu, Yourgos Goudaroulis & P. Nicolacopolous (eds.), Imre Lakatos and Theories of Scientific Change, Reidel. pp. 305-22. 1989.
  •  141
    Can a present or future event bring about a past event? An answer to this question is demanded by many other interesting questions. Can anybody, even a god, do anything about what has already occurred? Should we plan for the past, as well as for the future? Can anybody precognise the future in a way quite different from normal prediction? Do the causal laws and the past jointly preclude free action? Does current physical theory entail a consistent version of backwards causation? Recent articles …Read more
  • Control
    In R. Durrant (ed.), Essays in Honour of Gwen Taylor, University of Otago Press. pp. 190-210. 1981.
  •  110
    Axiological atomism
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 79 (3). 2001.
    Value is either additive or else it is subject to organic unity. In general we have organic unity where a complex whole is not simply the sum of its parts. Value exhibits organic unity if the value of a complex, whether a complex state or complex quality, is greater or less than the sum of the values of its components or parts. Whether or not value is additive might be thought to be of purely metaphysical interest, but it is also connected with important aspects of evaluative reasoning. Additivi…Read more
  • Values education
    In Harvey Siegel (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Education, Oxford University Press. 2009.
  •  180
    Truthlikeness
    Stanford Encyclopedia. 2014.
    Truth is the aim of inquiry. Nevertheless, some falsehoods seem to realize this aim better than others. Some truths better realize the aim than other truths. And perhaps even some falsehoods realize the aim better than some truths do. The dichotomy of the class of propositions into truths and falsehoods should thus be supplemented with a more fine-grained ordering — one which classifies propositions according to their closeness to the truth, their degree of truthlikeness or verisimilitude. The l…Read more
  •  40
    Permanent possibilities of sensation
    Philosophical Studies 98 (3): 345-359. 2000.
  •  2
    Truth and Truthlikeness
    In Glanzberg M. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Truth, Oxford University Press. forthcoming.
  • Experiences of value
    In Charles R. Pigden (ed.), Hume on Motivation and Virtue, Palgrave-macmillan. pp. 121. 2009.
  •  53
    Likeness to Truth
    Reidel. 1986.
    What does it take for one proposition to be closer to the truth than another. In this, the first published monograph on the topic, Oddie develops a comprehensive theory that takes the likeness in truthlikeness seriously.
  •  33
    Reasons from Within (review)
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 9 (3): 473-476. 2012.
  •  468
    What Do we See in Museums?
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 79 217-240. 2016.
    I address two related questions. First: what value is there in visiting a museum and becoming acquainted with the objects on display? For art museums the answer seems obvious: we go to experience valuable works of art, and experiencing valuable works of art is itself valuable. In this paper I focus on non-art museums, and while these may house aesthetically valuable objects, that is not their primary purpose, and at least some of the objects they house might not be particularly aesthetically val…Read more
  •  74
    What's wrong?: applied ethicists and their critics (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2004.
    What's Wrong?: Applied Ethicists and Their Critics is a thorough and engaging introduction to applied ethics that covers virtually all of the issues in the field. Featuring more than ninety-five articles, it addresses standard topics--such as abortion, euthanasia, capital punishment, world hunger, and animal rights--and also delves into cutting-edge areas like cloning, racial profiling, same-sex marriage, prostitution, and slave reparations. The volume includes seminal essays by prominent philos…Read more
  •  19
    The Unity of Theories
    In Fred D'Agostino & I. C. Jarvie (eds.), Freedom and Rationality, Reidel. pp. 343--368. 1989.
  •  3
    The moral case for the legalization of voluntary euthanasia
    Victoria University of Wellington Law Review 28 207-24. 1998.
  • Pavel Tichý
    A Companion to Philosophy in Australia and New Zealand. 2010.
  •  266
    Conditionalization, cogency, and cognitive value
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48 (4): 533-541. 1997.
    Why should a Bayesian bother performing an experiment, one the result of which might well upset his own favored credence function? The Ramsey-Good theorem provides a decision theoretic answer. Provided you base your decision on expected utility, and the the experiment is cost-free, performing the experiment and then choosing has at least as much expected utility as choosing without further ado. Furthermore, doing the experiment is strictly preferable just in case at least one possible outcome …Read more
  • Control, consequence and compatibilism
    In T. Childers (ed.), Between Words and Worlds, Filosofia. pp. 143-56. 2000.
  •  38
    The core of the truthmaker research program is that true propositions are made true by appropriate parts of the actual world. This idea seems to give realists their best shot at capturing a robust account of the dependence of truth on the world. For a part of the world to be a truthmaker for a particular it must suffice for, or necessitate, the truth of the proposition. There are two extreme and unsatisfactory truthmaker theories. At one extreme any part of the world (up to and including the who…Read more
  •  64
    Verisimilitude reviewed
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 32 (3): 237-265. 1981.
  •  67
    The aesthetic adequacy of copies
    with David Ward
    British Journal of Aesthetics 29 (3): 258-260. 1989.
  •  12
    Is Science Progressive (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (2): 272-276. 1987.