•  155
    Prescriptions Are Assertions: An Essay on Moral Syntax
    American Philosophical Quarterly 35 (1). 1998.
  •  28
    Commonsense Darwinism (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 64 (4): 868-871. 2011.
  •  221
    Virtue epistemology and the epistemology of virtue
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (1): 23-43. 2000.
    The ancient Greeks almost universally accepted the thesis that virtues are skills. Skills have an underlying intellectual structure , and having a particular skill entails understanding the relevant logos. possessing a general ability to diagnose and solve problems . as well as having appropriate experience. Two implications of accepting this thesis for moral epistemology and epistemology in general are considered. Thinking of virtues as skills yields a viable virtue epistemology in which moral …Read more
  •  230
    Two dogmas of metaethics
    Philosophical Studies 132 (3): 439-466. 2007.
    The two dogmas at issue are the Humean dogma that “‘is’ statements do not imply ‘ought’ statements” and the Kantian dogma that “‘ought’ statements imply ‘can’” statements. The extant literature concludes these logically contradict each other. On the contrary, it is argued here that while there is no derivable formal contradiction, the juxtaposition of the dogmas manifests a philosophical disagreement over how to understand the logic of prescriptions. This disagreement bears on how to understand …Read more
  •  101
    Moral Reality
    Oxford University Press. 2001.
    We typically assume that the standard for what is beautiful lies in the eye of the beholder. Yet this is not the case when we consider morality; what we deem morally good is not usually a matter of opinion. Such thoughts push us toward being realists about moral properties, but a cogent theory of moral realism has long been an elusive philosophical goal. Paul Bloomfield here offers a rigorous defense of moral realism, developing an ontology for morality that models the property of being morally …Read more
  •  280
    Error Theory and the Concept of Morality
    Metaphilosophy 44 (4): 451-469. 2013.
    Error theories about morality often take as their starting point the supposed queerness of morality, and those resisting these arguments often try to argue by analogy that morality is no more queer than other unproblematic subject matters. Here, error theory (as exemplified primarily by the work of Richard Joyce) is resisted first by arguing that it assumes a common, modern, and peculiarly social conception of morality. Then error theorists point out that the social nature of morality requires o…Read more
  •  31
    Moral Realism And Program Explanation: A Very Short Symposium 2: Reply To Miller
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 87 (2): 343-344. 2009.
    Miller's reply to Nelson misses the point because it does not attend to the difference between identifying the truth conditions for a proposition and explaining why those conditions are the ones in which the proposition is true
  •  7
    The Normative Web (review)
    Social Theory and Practice 36 (1): 157-164. 2010.
  •  35
    Partially Re-Humanized Ethics: Comments on Butchvarov
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1): 184-189. 2003.
  •  133
    Morality and Self-Interest (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2008.
    The volume will act as a useful collection of scholarship by top figures, and as a resource and course book on an important topic.
  •  37
    Partially Re‐Humanized Ethics: Comments on Butchvarov
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1): 184-189. 2003.
  •  162
    Virtue Epistemology and the Epistemology of Virtue
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (1): 23-43. 2000.
    The ancient Greeks almost universally accepted the thesis that virtues are skills. Skills have an underlying intellectual structure (logos), and having a particular skill entails understanding the relevant logos. possessing a general ability to diagnose and solve problems (phronesis). as well as having appropriate experience. Two implications of accepting this thesis for moral epistemology and epistemology in general are considered. Thinking of virtues as skills yields a viable virtue epistemolo…Read more
  •  103
    The harm of immorality
    Ratio 21 (3): 241-259. 2008.
    A central problem in moral theory is how it is to be defended against those who think that there is no harm in being immoral, and that immorality can be in one's self-interest, assuming the perpetrator is not caught and punished. The argument presented here defends the idea that being immoral prevents one from having self-respect. If it makes sense to think that one cannot be happy without self-respect, then the conclusion follows that one cannot be both immoral and happy. Immorality is harmful …Read more
  •  103
    Of Goodness and Healthiness: A Viable Moral Ontology
    Philosophical Studies 87 (3): 309-332. 1997.
  •  94
    Good To Be Bad?
    Think 14 (40): 51-55. 2015.
  •  137
    The Rules of "Goodness": An Essay on Moral Semantics
    American Philosophical Quarterly 40 (3). 2003.
  •  53
    Review: David Wong: Natural Moralities (review)
    Mind 118 (469): 225-230. 2009.