•  140
    Wings, Spoons, Pills, and Quills
    Journal of Philosophy 96 (4): 191-206. 1999.
  • Pojecia syntetyczne. Filozoficzne rozwazania o kategoryzacji
    Roczniki Filozoficzne 43 (1): 165. 1995.
  • The Jean-Nicod Lectures 2002
  •  30
  •  257
    II—Ruth Garrett Millikan: Loosing the Word–Concept Tie
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 85 (1): 125-143. 2011.
    Sainsbury and Tye (2011) propose that, in the case of names and other simple extensional terms, we should substitute for Frege's second level of content—for his senses—a second level of meaning vehicle—words in the language of thought. I agree. They also offer a theory of atomic concept reference—their ‘originalist’ theory—which implies that people knowing the same word have the ‘same concept’. This I reject, arguing for a symmetrical rather than an originalist theory of concept reference, claim…Read more
  •  29
    Of what use categories?
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4): 663-664. 1986.
  •  42
    A theory of representation to complement TEC
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (5): 894-895. 2001.
    The target article can be strengthened by supplementing it with a better theory of mental representation. Given such a theory, there is reason to suppose that, first, even the most primitive representations are mostly of distal affairs; second, the most primitive representations also turn out to be directed two ways at once, both stating facts and directing action.
  •  23
    Embedded rationality
    In Murat Aydede & P. Robbins (eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition, Cambridge University Press. pp. 171--183. 2009.
  •  305
    On Knowing the Meaning; With a Coda on Swampman
    Mind 119 (473): 43-81. 2010.
    I give an analysis of how empirical terms do their work in communication and the gathering of knowledge that is fully externalist and that covers the full range of empirical terms. It rests on claims about ontology. A result is that armchair analysis fails as a tool for examining meanings of ‘basic’ empirical terms because their meanings are not determined by common methods or criteria of application passed from old to new users, by conventionally determined ‘intensions’. Nor do methods of appli…Read more
  •  1174
    On Reading Signs; Some Differences between Us and The Others If there are certain kinds of signs that an animal cannot learn to interpret, that might be for any of a number of reasons. It might be, first, because the animal cannot discriminate the signs from one another. For example, although human babies learn to discriminate human speech sounds according to the phonological structures of their native languages very easily, it may be that few if any other animals are capable of fully grasping t…Read more
  •  89
    The language-thought partnership: A Bird's eye view
    Language and Communication 21 (2): 157-166. 2001.
    I sketch in miniature the whole of my work on the relation between language and thought. Previously I have offered closeups of this terrain in various papers and books, and I reference them freely. But my main purpose here is to explain the relations among the parts, hoping this can serve as a short introduction to my work on language and thought for some, and for others as a clarification of the larger plan
  •  62
    Cutting Philosophy of Language Down to Size
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 48 125-140. 2001.
    When asked to contribute to this lecture series, my first thought was to talk about philosophy of biology, a new and increasingly influential field in philosophy, surely destined to have great impact in the coming years. But when a preliminary schedule for the series was circulated, I noticed that no one was speaking on language. Given the hegemony of philosophy of language at mid-century, after ‘the linguistic turn’, this seemed to require comment. How did philosophy of language achieve such st…Read more
  •  46
    Reply to Rosenberg (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (3). 2007.
  • The Nicod Lectures book.
  •  73
    Knowing What I'm Thinking Of
    with Andrew Woodfield
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 67 (1): 91-124. 1993.
  •  144
    Representations, targets and attitudes
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (1): 103-111. 2000.
  • The Jean-Nicod Lectures 2002
  •  83
    Précis of varieties of meaning (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (3). 2007.
  • The Jean-Nicod Lectures 2002
  •  79
    Useless content
    In Graham Macdonald & David Papineau (eds.), Teleosemantics, Oxford University Press. 2006.
  •  5
    Introduction
    Axiomathes 13 (3): 231-237. 2003.
    Introduction to Millikan's Jean Nicod lectures 2002.
  •  266
    On swampkinds
    Mind and Language 11 (1): 103-17. 1996.
    Suppose lightning strikes a dead tree in a swamp; I am standing nearby. My body is reduced to its elements, while entirely by coincidence (and out of different molecules) the tree is turned into my physical replica. My replica, The Swampman.....moves into my house and seems to write articles on radical interpretation. No one can tell the difference
  •  223
    Lewis’s view of the way conventions are passed on may have some especially interesting consequences for the study of language. I’ll start by briefly discussing agreements and disagreements that I have with Lewis’s general views on conventions and then turn to how linguistic conventions spread. I’ll compare views of main stream generative linguistics, in particular, Chomsky’s views on how syntactic forms are passed on, with the sort of view of language acquisition and language change advocated by…Read more
  • Empirical Identity
    Dissertation, Yale University. 1969.
  •  39
    Naturalist Reflections on Knowledge
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 65 (4): 315-334. 1984.
  •  60
    Seismograph Readings for explaining behavior
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50 (4): 807-812. 1990.