•  64
    Some social features of cognition
    Synthese 73 (1). 1987.
    This paper describes and assesses a number of dispositions which are instrumental in allowing us to take on the opinions of others unselfconsciously. It is argued that these dispositions are in fact reliable in the environments in which they tend to come into play. In addition, it is argued that agents are, by their own lights, justified in the beliefs they arrive at as a result of these processes. Finally, these processes are argued to provide a basis for rejecting the claim that fixation of be…Read more
  •  156
    Introspection and misdirection
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 67 (4). 1989.
    Internalist theories of justification put introspection to work in service of the task of error detection. Introspecting to determine whether our beliefs are well-supported by reasons is supposed to reveal where it is that our beliefs fail to measure up to appropriate standards. Internalists do not, however, offer any empirical evidence that introspection can constructively play this role. This chapter examines relevant evidence from social psychology about the way in which introspection actu…Read more
  •  55
    Replies to Alvin Goldman, Martin Kusch and William Talbott (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (2). 2005.
  •  522
    Epistemic normativity
    Synthese 94 (3). 1993.
    This paper examines the source and content of epistemic norms. In virtue of what is it that epistemic norms have their normative force? A semantic approach to this question, due to Alvin Goldman, is examined and found unacceptable. Instead, accounts seeking to ground epistemic norms in our desires are argued to be most promising. All of these accounts make epistemic norms a variety of hypothetical imperative. It is argued that such an account may be offered, grounding our epistemic norms in desi…Read more
  •  2
    Books reviews
    Mind 101 (401): 188-191. 1992.
  •  150
    Naturalistic Epistemology and Its Critics
    Philosophical Topics 23 (1): 237-255. 1995.
  •  228
    Timothy Williamson's the philosophy of philosophy
    Analysis 69 (1): 109-116. 2009.
    Timothy Williamson's new book, The Philosophy of Philosophy, has a number of central themes. The very idea that philosophy has a method which is different in kind from the sciences is one Williamson rejects. “… the common assumption of philosophical exceptionalism is false. Even the distinction between the a priori and the a posteriori turns out to obscure underlying similarities”. Although Williamson sees the book as “a defense of armchair philosophy”, he also argues that “the differences in su…Read more
  •  18
    Knowledge in Humans and Other Animals
    Noûs 33 (s13): 327-346. 1999.
  •  158
    Sosa in perspective
    Philosophical Studies 144 (1): 127--136. 2009.
    Ernest Sosa draws a distinction between animal knowledge and reflective knowledge, and this distinction forms the centerpiece of his new book, A Virtue Epistemology . This paper argues that the distinction cannot do the work which Sosa assigns to it.
  •  102
    How internal can you get?
    Synthese 74 (3). 1988.
    This paper examines Laurence BonJour''s defense of internalism inThe Structure of Empirical Knowledge with an eye toward better understanding the issues which separate internalists from externalists. It is argued that BonJour''s Doxastic Presumption cannot play the role which is required of it to make his internalism work. It is further argued that BonJour''s internalism, and, indeed, all other internalisms, are motivated by a Cartesian view of an agent''s access to her own mental states. This C…Read more
  •  354
  •  12
    Reasons and Knowledge
    Philosophical Review 92 (3): 460. 1983.
  •  6
    Appeals to intuition and the ambitions of epistemology
    In Stephen Hetherington (ed.), Epistemology Futures, Oxford University Press. pp. 10--25. 2006.
  •  828
    Naturalism and intuitions
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 74 (1): 27-49. 2007.
    This paper examines the relationship between methodological naturalism and the standard practice within philosophy of constructing theories on the basis of our intuitions about imaginary cases, especially in the work of Alvin Goldman. It is argued that current work in cognitive science presents serious problems for Goldman's approach.
  •  192
    The role of reasons in epistemology
    Episteme 12 (2): 225-239. 2015.
    The notion of a reason often plays a central role in epistemological theories. Justification is often explained in terms of the having of appropriate reasons, and a variety of epistemological distinctions are most naturally explained, it seems, by adverting to reasons. This paper examines the extent to which we may, instead, make do without appeal to such a notion. It is argued that the extent to which the notion of a reason should play an important role in epistemological theorizing will depend…Read more
  •  27
    The Contextualist Evasion of Epistemology
    Philosophical Issues 10 (1): 24-32. 2000.
  •  46
    In defense of deductive inference
    Philosophical Studies 76 (2-3). 1994.
  •  75
    Epistemic obligation and the possibility of internalism
    In Abrol Fairweather & Linda Trinkaus Zagzebski (eds.), Virtue Epistemology: Essays on Epistemic Virtue and Responsibility, Oxford University Press. pp. 231--248. 2001.
  •  112
    On Reflection
    Oxford University Press. 2012.
    Hilary Kornblith presents a new account of mental reflection, and its importance for knowledge, reasoning, freedom, and normativity. He argues that reflection cannot solve the philosophical problems it has traditionally been thought to, and offers a more realistic, demystified view of its nature which draws on dual process approaches to cognition
  •  161
    What is it like to be me?
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76 (1): 48-60. 1998.
    Introspection plays an ineliminable role in affording us with self-knowledge, or so it is widely believed. It is argued here that introspective evidence, by itself, is often insufficient to ground reasonable belief about many of our mental states, and the knowledge we do have of much of our mental life is crucially dependent on other sources.
  •  20
    Goldman and his Critics (edited book)
    Blackwell. 2016.
    Goldman and His Critics presents a series of original essays contributed by influential philosophers who critically examine Alvin Goldman’s work, followed by Goldman’s responses to each essay. Critiques Alvin Goldman’s groundbreaking theories, writings, and ideas on a range of philosophical topics Features contributions from some of the most important and influential contemporary philosophers Covers Goldman’s views on epistemology—both individual and social—in addition to cognitive science and m…Read more
  •  40
    Knowledge needs no justification
    In Quentin Smith (ed.), Epistemology: new essays, Oxford University Press. pp. 5--23. 2008.
    The Standard View in epistemology is that knowledge is justified, true belief plus something else. This chapter argues that Standard View should be rejected: knowledge does not require justification. The nature of knowledge and the nature of justification can be better understood if we stop viewing justification as one of the necessary conditions for knowledge.