•  183
    Opacity and Self-Consciousness
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 40 (2): 243-251. 2002.
  •  6
    Perception and Objective Knowledge
    The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 5 29-38. 2000.
    McDowell and Putnam are right to insist that objective knowledge is possible only because we are open to the world in perception, but neither of them offers an adequate account of the relationship between perception and perceptual judgments (which are at the core of our most fundamental knowledge of the world). This paper, intended as a contribution to the development of a sophisticated commonsense realism, proposes an account in terms of which perceptions acquire the status of perceptual judgme…Read more
  • This paper criticizes act-object accounts of experience and defends a version of the adverbial theory that is based on the assumption that sensory experiences always have propositional contents—in the sense that they do not represent bare individuals and properties, but whole states of affairs.
  •  82
    Content and Causation in Perception
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (4): 767-785. 1994.
    In order to perceive something, one must have a sense experience which it causes and which has a content that fits it appropriately. But veridical hallucinations show that more is required, viz., that the experience must also be caused by the object of perception in the right sort of way. The best account of what this amounts to is that the object causes the experience by means of a “reliable mechanism,” i.e., a causal mechanism which is generally apt to connect objects to experiences with conte…Read more
  •  94
    Capitalist Exploitation, Self-Ownership, and Equality
    with Peter Hudson and Darrel Moellendorf
    Philosophical Forum 32 (3). 2001.
    Traditional Marxists hold that capitalist modes of production are unjustly exploitative. In 'Self-Ownership, Freedom and Equality' G. A. Cohen argues that this ``exploitation charge'' commits traditional Marxists to the thesis that people own themselves (``self-ownership''). If so, then traditional Marxism is vulnerable to a libertarian challenge to its commitment to equality. Cohen, therefore, recommends that Marxists abandon the exploitation charge. This paper undermines Cohen's case for the a…Read more
  •  13
    This book explains Kant's major claims in the Critique of Pure Reason, how they hang together, and how Kant supports them, clarifying the way in which his reasoning unfolds over the course of this groundbreaking work. The book concentrates on key parts of the B edition that are essential to a basic understanding of Kant's project and provides a sympathetic account of Kant's reasoning about perception, space, time, judgment, substance, causation, objectivity, synthetic a priori knowledge, and the…Read more
  •  39
    A Kantian Account of Animal Cognition
    Philosophical Forum 48 (4): 369-393. 2017.
    Kant holds that “on the basis of their actions” we can infer that “animals act in accordance with representations” (Critique of the Power of Judgment, 5: 464, fn.). Animals, like humans, have the powers of sensibility, imagination and choice, but lack the human powers of understanding, reason and free choice. They also lack first-person representation, consciousness, concepts and inner sense. Nevertheless, animals have an analog of reason that involves connections of representations that explain…Read more
  •  44
    Perception and Objective Knowledge
    In The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy, Charlottesville: Philosophy Documentation Center. pp. 29-38. 2000.
    McDowell and Putnam are right to insist that objective knowledge is possible only because we are open to the world in perception, but neither of them offers an adequate account of the relationship between perception and perceptual judgments (which are at the core of our most fundamental knowledge of the world). This paper, intended as a contribution to the development of a sophisticated commonsense realism, proposes an account in terms of which perceptions acquire the status of perceptual judgme…Read more
  • Semantics for Conditionals
    Dissertation, University of the Witwatersrand, Johannesburg (South Africa). 1976.
  • Believing
    Dissertation, Indiana University. 1980.
    The emphasis in Part II is on the truth conditions of belief sentences. The chief aim is to show how the ontological account of belief advanced in Part I can serve as a basis for a theory of truth conditions for such sentences. The formal theory developed in Part II can, however, be discussed without reference to the earlier ontology. Chapter 11 presents the basic framework for the theory, and also deals with the truth conditions of the belief sentences which are construed as basic. In the later…Read more
  •  38
    Necessary Identity
    Philosophical Papers 4 (1): 12-20. 1975.
  •  211
    Reasons in Action
    Philosophical Papers 42 (3). 2013.
    When an agent performs an action because she takes something as a reason to do so, does she take it as a normative reason for the action or as an explanatory reason? In Reasons Without Rationalism, Setiya criticizes the normative view and advances a version of the explanatory view. This paper advances a version of the normative view and shows that it is not subject to Setiya's criticisms. It also shows that Setiya's explanatory account is subject to two fatal flaws, viz., that it raises question…Read more
  •  380
    Making Sense of Kant’s Schematism
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (4): 777-797. 1995.
    In this paper I advance an account of Kant’s Schematism according to which a schema in general is a pattern of imaginative synthesis that explains how intuitions have the content required for them to fall under a concept corresponding to the schema. An empirical schema is a pattern of imaginative synthesis that is responsive to the qualities of the sensations involved in the intuition which it synthesizes. A transcendental schema, in contrast, is not responsive to the particular qualities of the…Read more
  •  26
    Hetherington on Possible Objects
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 63 (4). 1985.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  53
    According to a common account, grammatical mood is merely a conventional indicator of force with no semantic significance. Focusing on indicatives, interrogatives and imperatives, I advance two reasons to reject this “force treatment” of mood. First, it can be shown that the mood of a subordinate clause can have semantic significance that affects the sense of a sentence in which it is embedded—which the force treatment cannot accommodate. Second, the speech acts of asserting, asking and ordering…Read more
  •  76
    Stalnaker on Inquiry
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 16 (3): 229-272. 1987.
    This article is an extended critical study of Robert C. Stalnaker, 'Inquiry' (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1984).
  •  132
    On the Semantics of Simple and Complex Demonstratives in English
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 39 (4): 487-505. 2001.
    According to a straightforward, conservative account of English demonstratives, simple and complex demonstratives are referring expressions belonging to the same semantic category (but they could be understood as either terms or quantifiers); the denotation of a complex demonstrative “dF” (if it has one) must satisfy the nominal “F” in “dF”; and both simple and complex demonstratives function as rigid designators. According to a recent alternative advanced by Lepore and Ludgwig, simple and compl…Read more
  •  261
    Intentionality and Normativity
    South African Journal of Philosophy 17 (2): 142-151. 1998.
    The intentionality of virtually all thought that is distinctive of human beings is linguistically based and constitutively normative. As Robert Brandom claims in Making It Explicit, this normativity is best understood as having roots in social practice. But Brandom is wrong to insist that all intentionality is normative (thus denying intentionality to nonhuman, nonlinguistic animals). For even the simple social practices that ground the most primate norms presuppose robust nonnormative intention…Read more
  •  1959
    The Role of Imagination in Perception
    South African Journal of Philosophy 15 (4): 133-138. 1996.
    This article is an explication and defense of Kant’s view that ‘imagination is a necessary ingredient of perception itself’ (Critique of Pure Reason, A120, fn.). Imagination comes into perception at a far more basic level than Strawson allows, and it is required for the constitution of intuitions (= sense experiences) out of sense impressions. It also plays an important part in explaining how it is possible for intuitions to have intentional contents. These functions do not involve the applicati…Read more
  •  29
    Russellian Thoughts
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48 (4): 669-682. 1988.
  •  9
    Opacity and Self‐Consciousness
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 40 (2): 243-251. 2002.
  •  25
    Heidelberger on the First and Second Person
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 46 (2): 323-331. 1985.
  •  47
    Thought and Language
    South African Journal of Philosophy 21 (3): 200-218. 2002.
    This article defends the view that nonlinguistic animals could be capable of thought (in the sense in which the mere possession of beliefs and desires is sufficient for thought). It is easy to identify flaws in Davidson's arguments for the thesis that thought depends upon language if one is open to the idea that some nonlinguistic animals have beliefs. It is, however, necessary to do more than this if one wishes to engage with the deeper challenge underlying Davidson's reasoning, viz., that of p…Read more
  •  1178
    Objectivism versus Realism
    Philosophical Forum 42 (1): 79-104. 2011.
    Realism about affirmations of a given type is the view that these affirmations are to be understood as assertions that attempt to describe a largely independent reality, and that they are correct if and only if they manage to do so (regardless of whether they can be known to be correct). Objectivisim about affirmations of a given type is the view that they are subject to adequate, non-arbitrary standards of correctness, and that there are a significant number of non-trivial affirmations of this …Read more
  •  303
    In Defense of Moderate Neutralism
    Journal of Social Philosophy 33 (3). 2002.
  •  45
    How Demonstratives Denote
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 22 (1): 91-104. 1984.
    Focusing on the simple demonstrative ‘that’ and demonstrative expressions of the form ‘that F,’ this paper reviews four accounts of what determines the denotations of demonstratives—the description theory, according to which the work is done by a proper definite description associated with the demonstrative; the causal theory, according to which it is done by a non-deviant causal chain connecting the object and the demonstrative; the demonstration theory, according to which it is done by a demon…Read more
  •  69
    Why Proper Names are Rigid Designators
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50 (3): 519-536. 1990.
  •  42
    Elementary Formal Semantics for English Tense and Aspect
    Philosophical Papers 21 (3): 215-241. 1992.
    This paper presents an approach to the elementary temporal semantics of the English tense system, the atoms of which are the present tense, the past tense, the progressive auxiliary, the perfective auxiliary, and the modal will as used for the future. It offers accounts of the forms of temporal semantics of core verb phrases of different categories and of the atoms of the tense system, using machinery that that yields appropriate compositional accounts of the temporal semantics of compound, tens…Read more