•  27
    Pictures, Titles, Depictive Content
    In David Wagner, Wolfram Pichler, Elisabeth Nemeth & Richard Heinrich (eds.), Publications of the Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society - N.S. 17, De Gruyter. pp. 395-408. 2011.
  •  256
    Aesthetics—what? Why? And wherefore?
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 65 (2). 2007.
    It is a very great honor to address my friends and colleagues as president of the American Society for Aesthetics, an organization that plays a unique role in a field that is, at once, a major traditional branch of philosophy and also central to disciplines often regarded as remote from philosophy, as well as depending crucially on their contributions
  •  4
    On pictures and photographs: objections answered
    In Richard Allen & Murray Smith (eds.), Film theory and philosophy, Oxford University Press. pp. 60--75. 1997.
  •  34
    Memesis As Make-Believe
    Harvard University Press. 1990.
  •  159
    What is abstract about the art of music?
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 46 (3): 351-364. 1988.
  •  27
    In fifteen essays-one new, two newly revised and expanded, three with new postscripts-Kendall L. Walton wrestles with philosophical issues concerning music, metaphor, empathy, existence, fiction, and expressiveness in the arts. These subjects are intertwined in striking and surprising ways. By exploring connections among them, appealing sometimes to notions of imagining oneself in shoes different from one's own, Walton creates a wide-ranging mosaic of innovative insights.
  • Empathy and Musical Tension
    In Dag Prawitz (ed.), Meaning and interpretation: conference held in Stockholm, September 24-26, 1998, Kungl. Vitterhets, Historie Och Antikvitets Akademien. pp. 55--43. 2002.
  •  909
    Prop oriented make-believe is make-believe utilized for the purpose of understanding what I call “props,” actual objects or states of affairs that make propositions “fictional,” true in the make-believe world. I, David Hills, and others have claimed that prop oriented make-believe lies at the heart of the functioning of many metaphors, and one variety of fictionalism in metaphysics invokes prop oriented make-believe to explain away apparent references to entities some find questionable or probl…Read more
  •  48
  •  19
    Morals in Fiction and Fictional Morality
    with Michael Tanner
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 68 (1): 27-66. 1994.
  •  28
    Linguistic relativity
    In Glenn Pearce & Patrick Maynard (eds.), Conceptual Change, D. Reidel. pp. 1--30. 1973.
  •  1019
    That photography is a supremely realistic medium may be the commonsense view, but—as Edward Steichen reminds us—it is by no means universal. Dissenters note how unlike reality a photograph is and how unlikely we are to confuse the one with the other. They point to “distortions” engendered by the photographic process and to the control which the photographer exercises over the finished product, the opportunities he enjoys for interpretation and falsification. Many emphasize the expressive nature …Read more
  •  99
    Fiction, Fiction-Making, and Styles of Fictionality
    Philosophy and Literature 7 (1): 78-88. 1983.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Kendall L. Walton FICTION, FICTION-MAKING, AND STYLES OF FICTIONALITY Both objectsandactions are said to have styles. Styles eire attributed to works of art, bathing suits, neckties, and automobiles. But we also think of styles as ways of doing things. There are styles of teaching, styles of chess playing, styles of travel. The primary notion of style is the one which attaches to actions. When we speak of die style of a poem or a por…Read more
  •  143
    Realist theories about fictional entities must explain the fact that, in ordinary contexts people deny, apparently in all seriousness, that there are such things as the Big Bad Wolf and Santa Claus. The usual explanation treats these denials as involving restricted quantification: The speaker is said to be denying only that the Big Bad Wolf and Santa Claus are to be found among real or actual things, not that there are no such things at all. This is unconvincing. The denials may just as naturall…Read more
  •  183
    Categories and intentions: A reply
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 32 (2): 267-268. 1973.
  •  300
    Pictures and make-believe
    Philosophical Review 82 (3): 283-319. 1973.
  •  5
    Mimesis as Make-Believe
    Synthese 109 (3): 413-434. 1996.
  •  86
    Thoughtwriting—in Poetry and Music
    In Kendall L. Walton (ed.), In Other Shoes: Music, Metaphor, Empathy, Existence, Oxford University Press. pp. 54-74. 2011/2015.
    Poetry is a literary art, and is often examined alongside the novel, stories, and theater. But poetry, much of it, has more in common with music, in important respects, than with other forms of literature. The emphasis on sound and rhythm in both poetry and music is obvious, but I will explore a very different similarity between them. All or almost all works of literary fiction have narrators—so it is said anyway—characters who, in the world of the fiction, utter or write the words of the text t…Read more
  •  17
    Erratum to: Meiosis, hyperbole, irony
    Philosophical Studies 174 (1): 121-121. 2017.
  •  31
    On Kendall Walton's Mimesis as Make-Believe
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (2): 383-387. 1991.
  •  93
    Marvelous images: on values and the arts
    Oxford University Press. 2008.
    The twelve essays by Kendall Walton in this volume address a broad range of issues concerning the arts. Walton introduces an innovative account of aesthetic value, and explores relations between aesthetic value and values of other kinds. His classic 'Categories of Art' is included, as is 'Transparent Pictures', his controversial account of what is special about photographs. A new essay investigates the fact that still pictures are still, although some of them depict motion. New postscripts have …Read more
  •  238
    Listening with imagination: Is music representational?
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 52 (1): 47-61. 1994.
  •  284
    Transparent Pictures: On the Nature of Photographic Realism
    Critical Inquiry 11 (2): 246-277. 1984.
    That photography is a supremely realistic medium may be the commonsense view, but—as Edward Steichen reminds us—it is by no means universal. Dissenters note how unlike reality a photograph is and how unlikely we are to confuse the one with the other. They point to “distortions” engendered by the photographic process and to the control which the photographer exercises over the finished product, the opportunities he enjoys for interpretation and falsification. Many emphasize the expressive nature …Read more
  •  443
    How marvelous! Toward a theory of aesthetic value
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 51 (3): 499-510. 1993.
  •  47
    Reply to Reviewers
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (2). 1991.
  •  2535
    Categories of Art
    Philosophical Review 79 (3): 334-367. 1970.