•  30
    Accuracy and actuality
    Erkenntnis 12 (2). 1978.
  •  112
    Maoist mathematics?
    Philosophia Mathematica 6 (3): 334-345. 1998.
  •  52
    Symbol systems and artistic styles
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 35 (3): 279-292. 1977.
  •  60
    Real analysis without classes
    Philosophia Mathematica 2 (3): 228-250. 1994.
    This paper explores strengths and limitations of both predicativism and nominalism, especially in connection with the problem of characterizing the continuum. Although the natural number structure can be recovered predicatively (despite appearances), no predicative system can characterize even the full predicative continuum which the classicist can recognize. It is shown, however, that the classical second-order theory of continua (third-order number theory) can be recovered nominalistically, by…Read more
  •  230
    Does category theory provide a framework for mathematical structuralism?
    Philosophia Mathematica 11 (2): 129-157. 2003.
    Category theory and topos theory have been seen as providing a structuralist framework for mathematics autonomous vis-a-vis set theory. It is argued here that these theories require a background logic of relations and substantive assumptions addressing mathematical existence of categories themselves. We propose a synthesis of Bell's many-topoi view and modal-structuralism. Surprisingly, a combination of mereology and plural quantification suffices to describe hypothetical large domains, recoveri…Read more
  •  49
    A plurality of approaches to foundational aspects of mathematics is a fact of life. Two loci of this are discussed here, the classicism/constructivism controversy over standards of proof, and the plurality of universes of discourse for mathematics arising in set theory and in category theory, whose problematic relationship is discussed. The first case illustrates the hypothesis that a sufficiently rich subject matter may require a multiplicity of approaches. The second case, while in some respects …Read more
  •  90
    Bayes and beyond
    Philosophy of Science 64 (2): 191-221. 1997.
    Several leading topics outstanding after John Earman's Bayes or Bust? are investigated further, with emphasis on the relevance of Bayesian explication in epistemology of science, despite certain limitations. (1) Dutch Book arguments are reformulated so that their independence from utility and preference in epistemic contexts is evident. (2) The Bayesian analysis of the Quine-Duhem problem is pursued; the phenomenon of a "protective belt" of auxiliary statements around reasonably successful theor…Read more
  •  60
    Never Say “Never”!
    Philosophical Topics 17 (2): 47-67. 1989.
  •  40
    The Classical Continuum without Points – CORRIGENDUM
    with S. Shapiro
    Review of Symbolic Logic 6 (3): 571-571. 2013.
  •  140
    Dualling: A critique of an argument of Popper and Miller
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37 (2): 220-223. 1986.
  • Solomon Feferman, in the light of logic
    Philosophia Mathematica 9 (2): 231-237. 2001.
  •  39
    After some metatheoretic preliminaries on questions of justification and rational reconstruction, we lay out some key desiderata for foundational frameworks for mathematics, some of which reflect recent discussions of pluralism and structuralism. Next we draw out some implications (pro and con) bearing on set theory and category and topos therory. Finally, we sketch a variant of a modal-structural core system, incorporating elements of predicativism and the systems of reverse mathematics, and co…Read more
  •  4
    Reason and Prediction
    Philosophical Review 84 (2): 273. 1975.
  •  98
    On the significance of the Burali-Forti paradox
    Analysis 71 (4): 631-637. 2011.
    After briefly reviewing the standard set-theoretic resolutions of the Burali-Forti paradox, we examine how the paradox arises in set theory formalized with plural quantifiers. A significant choice emerges between the desirable unrestricted availability of ordinals to represent well-orderings and the sensibility of attempting to refer to ‘absolutely all ordinals’ or ‘absolutely all well-orderings’. This choice is obscured by standard set theories, which rely on type distinctions which are obliter…Read more
  •  123
    What is categorical structuralism?
    In Johan van Benthem, Gerhard Heinzman, M. Rebushi & H. Visser (eds.), The Age of Alternative Logics, Springer. pp. 151--161. 2006.
  • Against 'Absolutely Everything'!
    In Agustín Rayo & Gabriel Uzquiano (eds.), Absolute Generality, Clarendon Press. 2006.
  •  128
    Mathematical Pluralism: The Case of Smooth Infinitesimal Analysis
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 35 (6): 621-651. 2006.
    A remarkable development in twentieth-century mathematics is smooth infinitesimal analysis ('SIA'), introducing nilsquare and nilpotent infinitesimals, recovering the bulk of scientifically applicable classical analysis ('CA') without resort to the method of limits. Formally, however, unlike Robinsonian 'nonstandard analysis', SIA conflicts with CA, deriving, e.g., 'not every quantity is either = 0 or not = 0.' Internally, consistency is maintained by using intuitionistic logic (without the law …Read more
  •  62
    With the rise of multiple geometries in the nineteenth century, and in the last century the rise of abstract algebra, of the axiomatic method, the set-theoretic foundations of mathematics, and the influential work of the Bourbaki, certain views called “structuralist” have become commonplace. Mathematics is seen as the investigation, by more or less rigorous deductive means, of “abstract structures”, systems of objects fulfilling certain structural relations among themselves and in relation to othe…Read more
  •  69
    Realist principles
    Philosophy of Science 50 (2): 227-249. 1983.
    We list, with discussions, various principles of scientific realism, in order to exhibit their diversity and to emphasize certain serious problems of formulation. Ontological and epistemological principles are distinguished. Within the former category, some framed in semantic terms (truth, reference) serve their purpose vis-a-vis instrumentalism (Part 1). They fail, however, to distinguish the realist from a wide variety of (constructional) empiricists. Part 2 seeks purely ontological formulatio…Read more
  •  45
    Quantum logic and the projection postulate
    Philosophy of Science 48 (3): 469-486. 1981.
    This paper explores the status of the von Neumann-Luders state transition rule (the "projection postulate") within "real-logic" quantum logic. The entire discussion proceeds from a reading of the Luders rule according to which, although idealized in applying only to "minimally disturbing" measurements, it nevertheless makes empirical claims and is not a purely mathematical theorem. An argument (due to Friedman and Putnam) is examined to the effect that QL has an explanatory advantage over Copenh…Read more
  •  125
    On nominalism
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62 (3): 691-705. 2001.
    Probably there is no position in Goodman’s corpus that has generated greater perplexity and criticism than Goodman’s “nominalism”. As is abundantly clear from Goodman’s writings, it is not “abstract entities” generally that he questions—indeed, he takes sensory qualia as “basic” in his Carnap-inspired constructional system in Structure—but rather just those abstracta that are so crystal clear in their identity conditions, so fundamental to our thought, so prevalent and seemingly unavoidable in o…Read more