•  36
    Gleason's theorem is not constructively provable
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 22 (2). 1993.
  •  68
    Along with Frege, Russell maintained an absolutist stance regarding the subject matter of mathematics, revealed rather than imposed, or proposed, by logical analysis. The Fregean definition of cardinal number, for example, is viewed as (essentially) correct, not merely adequate for mathematics. And Dedekind’s “structuralist” views come in for criticism in the Principles. But, on reflection, Russell also flirted with views very close to a (different) version of structuralism. Main varieties of modern…Read more
  •  23
    Determination and Logical Truth
    Journal of Philosophy 82 (11): 607-616. 1985.
  •  191
    Predicativism as a Philosophical Position
    Revue Internationale de Philosophie 3 295-312. 2004.
  •  49
    Neither categorical nor set-theoretic foundations
    Review of Symbolic Logic 6 (1): 16-23. 2013.
    First we review highlights of the ongoing debate about foundations of category theory, beginning with Fefermantop-down” approach, where particular categories and functors need not be explicitly defined. Possible reasons for resisting the proposal are offered and countered. The upshot is to sustain a pluralism of foundations along lines actually foreseen by Feferman (1977), something that should be welcomed as a way of resolving this long-standing debate
  •  245
    The classical continuum without points
    Review of Symbolic Logic 6 (3): 488-512. 2013.
    We develop a point-free construction of the classical one- dimensional continuum, with an interval structure based on mereology and either a weak set theory or logic of plural quantification. In some respects this realizes ideas going back to Aristotle,although, unlike Aristotle, we make free use of classical "actual infinity". Also, in contrast to intuitionistic, Bishop, and smooth infinitesimal analysis, we follow classical analysis in allowing partitioning of our "gunky line" into mutually ex…Read more
  •  32
    1995–1996 annual meeting of the association for symbolic logic
    with Tomek Bartoszynski, Harvey Friedman, Bakhadyr Khoussainov, Phokion G. Kolaitis, Richard Shore, Charles Steinhorn, Mirna Dzamonja, Itay Neeman, and Slawomir Solecki
    Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 2 (4): 448-472. 1996.
  •  68
    Standard proofs of generalized Bell theorems, aiming to restrict stochastic, local hidden-variable theories for quantum correlation phenomena, employ as a locality condition the requirement of conditional stochastic independence. The connection between this and the no-superluminary-action requirement of the special theory of relativity has been a topic of controversy. In this paper, we introduce an alternative locality condition for stochastic theories, framed in terms of the models of such a th…Read more
  •  6
    Reply to Comments of Solomon Ferferman
    Revue Internationale de Philosophie 3 325-328. 2004.
  •  8
    From Constructive to Predicative Mathematics
    In John Earman & John Norton (eds.), The Cosmos of Science, University of Pittsburgh Press. pp. 6--153. 1997.
  •  103
    As argued in Hellman (1993), the theorem of Pour-El and Richards (1983) can be seen by the classicist as limiting constructivist efforts to recover the mathematics for quantum mechanics. Although Bridges (1995) may be right that the constructivist would work with a different definition of 'closed operator', this does not affect my point that neither the classical unbounded operators standardly recognized in quantum mechanics nor their restrictions to constructive arguments are recognizable as ob…Read more
  •  38
    Corrigendum
    Synthese 53 (3): 504-504. 1982.
  •  17
    On the Scope and Force of Indispensability Arguments
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1992 456-464. 1992.
    Three questions are highlighted concerning the scope and force of indispensability arguments supporting classical, infinitistic mathematics. The first concerns the need for non-constructive reasoning for scientifically applicable mathematics; the second concerns the need for impredicative set existence principles for finitistic and scientifically applicable mathematics, respectively; and the third concerns the general status of such arguments in light of recent work in mathematical logic, especi…Read more
  •  236
    Three varieties of mathematical structuralism
    Philosophia Mathematica 9 (2): 184-211. 2001.
    Three principal varieties of mathematical structuralism are compared: set-theoretic structuralism (‘STS’) using model theory, Shapiro's ante rem structuralism invoking sui generis universals (‘SGS’), and the author's modal-structuralism (‘MS’) invoking logical possibility. Several problems affecting STS are discussed concerning, e.g., multiplicity of universes. SGS overcomes these; but it faces further problems of its own, concerning, e.g., the very intelligibility of purely structural objects a…Read more
  •  30
    Accuracy and actuality
    Erkenntnis 12 (2). 1978.
  •  112
    Maoist mathematics?
    Philosophia Mathematica 6 (3): 334-345. 1998.
  •  52
    Symbol systems and artistic styles
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 35 (3): 279-292. 1977.
  •  60
    Real analysis without classes
    Philosophia Mathematica 2 (3): 228-250. 1994.
    This paper explores strengths and limitations of both predicativism and nominalism, especially in connection with the problem of characterizing the continuum. Although the natural number structure can be recovered predicatively (despite appearances), no predicative system can characterize even the full predicative continuum which the classicist can recognize. It is shown, however, that the classical second-order theory of continua (third-order number theory) can be recovered nominalistically, by…Read more
  •  230
    Does category theory provide a framework for mathematical structuralism?
    Philosophia Mathematica 11 (2): 129-157. 2003.
    Category theory and topos theory have been seen as providing a structuralist framework for mathematics autonomous vis-a-vis set theory. It is argued here that these theories require a background logic of relations and substantive assumptions addressing mathematical existence of categories themselves. We propose a synthesis of Bell's many-topoi view and modal-structuralism. Surprisingly, a combination of mereology and plural quantification suffices to describe hypothetical large domains, recoveri…Read more
  •  49
    A plurality of approaches to foundational aspects of mathematics is a fact of life. Two loci of this are discussed here, the classicism/constructivism controversy over standards of proof, and the plurality of universes of discourse for mathematics arising in set theory and in category theory, whose problematic relationship is discussed. The first case illustrates the hypothesis that a sufficiently rich subject matter may require a multiplicity of approaches. The second case, while in some respects …Read more
  •  90
    Bayes and beyond
    Philosophy of Science 64 (2): 191-221. 1997.
    Several leading topics outstanding after John Earman's Bayes or Bust? are investigated further, with emphasis on the relevance of Bayesian explication in epistemology of science, despite certain limitations. (1) Dutch Book arguments are reformulated so that their independence from utility and preference in epistemic contexts is evident. (2) The Bayesian analysis of the Quine-Duhem problem is pursued; the phenomenon of a "protective belt" of auxiliary statements around reasonably successful theor…Read more
  •  61
    Never Say “Never”!
    Philosophical Topics 17 (2): 47-67. 1989.
  •  40
    The Classical Continuum without Points – CORRIGENDUM
    with S. Shapiro
    Review of Symbolic Logic 6 (3): 571-571. 2013.
  •  140
    Dualling: A critique of an argument of Popper and Miller
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37 (2): 220-223. 1986.
  • Solomon Feferman, in the light of logic
    Philosophia Mathematica 9 (2): 231-237. 2001.