•  79
    Utility and framing
    Synthese 176 (1). 2010.
    Standard principles of rational decision assume that an option's utility is both comprehensive and accessible. These features constrain interpretations of an option's utility. This essay presents a way of understanding utility and laws of utility. It explains the relation between an option's utility and its outcome's utility and argues that an option's utility is relative to a specification of the option. Utility's relativity explains how a decision problem's framing affects an option's utility …Read more
  •  95
    Causal decision theory
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2009.
  •  30
    Introduction
    Synthese 176 (1): 1-3. 2010.
    This introduction is to a special journal issue on realistic standards for decisions. A realistic standard takes account of human cognitive limits, the circumstances for making a decision, and the features of a decision problem.
  •  14
    The General Welfare As A Constitutional Goal
    Social Philosophy Today 5 411-432. 1991.
    This essay examines how attention to the general welfare should influence the formulation of a constitution.
  •  79
    Collective acts
    Synthese 187 (1): 223-241. 2012.
    Groups of people perform acts. For example, a committee passes a resolution, a team wins a game, and an orchestra performs a symphony. These collective acts may be evaluated for rationality. Take a committee’s passing a resolution. This act may be evaluated not only for fairness but also for rationality. Did it take account of all available information? Is the resolution consistent with the committee’s past resolutions? Standards of collective rationality apply to collective acts, that is, acts …Read more
  • This book review describes and evaluates the essays collected by the editors.
  •  72
    Risk's Place in Decision Rules
    Synthese 126 (3): 427-441. 2001.
    To handle epistemic and pragmatic risks, Gärdenfors and Sahlin (1982, 1988) design a decision procedure for cases in which probabilities are indeterminate. Their procedure steps outside the traditional expected utility framework. Must it do this? Can the traditional framework handle risk? This paper argues that it can. The key is a comprehensive interpretation of an option's possible outcomes. Taking possible outcomes more broadly than Gärdenfors and Sahlin do, expected utility can give risk its…Read more
  •  27
    Adam Morton on Dilemmas
    Dialogue 33 (1): 95. 1994.
    Adam Morton offers a novel approach to making decisions. This review describes and evaluates his innovations
  •  89
    Decision theory aims at a general account of rationality covering humans but to begin makes idealizations about decision problems and agents' resources and circumstances. It treats inerrant agents with unlimited cognitive power facing tractable decision problems. This book systematically rolls back idealizations and without loss of precision treats errant agents with limited cognitive abilities facing decision problems without a stable top option. It recommends choices that maximize utility usin…Read more
  •  20
    This book review describes and evaluates John Pollock's view about rational decision-making.
  •  22
    Decisions in Dynamic Settings
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1986. 1986.
    In a decision problem with a dynamic setting there is at least one option whose realization would change the expected utilities of options by changing the probability or utility function with respect to which the expected utilities of options are computed. A familiar example is Newcomb's problem. William Harper proposes a generalization of causal decision theory intended to cover all decision problems with dynamic settings, not just Newcomb's problem. His generalization uses Richard Jeffrey's id…Read more
  •  2
    Mark Kaplan, Decision Theory as Philosophy (review)
    Philosophy in Review 16 (3): 179-180. 1996.
    Mark Kaplan proposes amending decision theory to accommodate better cases in which an agent's probability assignment is imprecise. The review describes and evaluates his proposals.
  •  20
    Value in Ethics and Economics (review)
    Philosophical Books 36 (2): 139-141. 1995.
    This review describes and evaluates a book by Elizabeth Anderson.
  •  79
    This paper summarizes and rebuts the three standard objections made by social choice theorists against interpersonal utility. The first objection argues that interpersonal utility is measningless. I show that this objection either focuses on irrelevant kinds of meaning or else uses implausible criteria of meaningfulness. The second objection argues that interpersonal utility has no role to play in social choice theory. I show that on the contrary interpersonal utility is useful in formulating go…Read more
  •  26
    The Standard of Living
    Philosophical Books 29 (3): 180-183. 1988.
    This book review evaluate Amartya Sen's views about capabilities and the standard of living.
  •  65
    Conventions and social institutions
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 27 (4): 599-618. 1989.
    This essay examines views of convention advanced by David Lewis and Margaret Gilbert.
  • Frederic Schick, Ambiguity and Logic Reviewed by
    Philosophy in Review 24 (3): 222-224. 2004.
  •  33
    The contributors
    Synthese 176 (1): 149-150. 2010.
    This lists the contributors to a special issue on realistic standards for decisions.
  •  16
    Economic theory may explain the behavior of animals. Its application to animals is not straightforward, however.
  •  22
  •  25
    Auguste Comte: Trajectoires positivistes 1798–1998 (review)
    Isis 96 470-471. 2005.
    Auguste Comte's version of positivism shares logical positivism's aversion to metaphysics.
  •  34
    Decisions without Sharp Probabilities
    Philosophia Scientiae 19 213-225. 2015.
    Adam Elga [Elga 2010] argues that no principle of rationality leads from unsharp probabilities to decisions. He concludes that a perfectly rational agent does not have unsharp probabilities. This paper defends unsharp probabilities. It shows how unsharp probabilities may ground rational decisions
  •  6
    Probabilities in decision rules
    In Ellery Eells & James H. Fetzer (eds.), The Place of Probability in Science, Springer. pp. 289--319. 2010.
    The theory of direct reference suggests revising probability theory so that a probability attaches to a proposition given a way of understanding the proposition. The revisions make probabilities relative but do not change their structure.
  •  1
    Models of Decision-Making: Simplifying Choices
    Cambridge University Press. 2014.
    The options in a decision problem generally have outcomes with common features. Putting aside the common features simplifies deliberations, but the simplification requires a philosophical justification that this book provides.
  •  302
    Conditional utility and its place in decision theory
    Journal of Philosophy 77 (11): 702-715. 1980.
    Causal decision theory attends to probabilities used to obtain an option's expected utility but for completeness should also attend to utilities of possible outcomes. A suitable formula for an option's expected utility uses a certain type of conditional utility.
  •  52
    Food products with genetically modified ingredients are common, yet many consumers are unaware of this. When polled, consumers say that they want to know whether their food contains GM ingredients, just as many want to know whether their food is natural or organic. Informing consumers is a major motivation for labeling. But labeling need not be mandatory. Consumers who want GM-free products will pay a premium to support voluntary labeling. Why do consumers want to know about GM ingredients? GM f…Read more
  • Comte et Mill sur l'économie politique
    Revue Internationale de Philosophie 52 (203): 79-93. 1998.
    This essay compares the views of Auguste Comte and John Stuart Mill on political economy.
  •  94
    Initiating coordination
    Philosophy of Science 74 (5): 790-801. 2007.
    How do rational agents coordinate in a single-stage, noncooperative game? Common knowledge of the payoff matrix and of each player's utility maximization among his strategies does not suffice. This paper argues that utility maximization among intentions and then acts generates coordination yielding a payoff-dominant Nash equilibrium. ‡I thank the audience at my paper's presentation at the 2006 PSA meeting for many insightful points. †To contact the author, please write to: Philosophy Department,…Read more