•  21
    Liberal Utilitarianism
    Philosophical Books 30 (3): 182-183. 1989.
    This book review describes and evaluates Jonathan Riley's views about utilitarianism.
  •  71
    Utility Maximization Generalized
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 5 (2): 282-299. 2008.
    Theories of rationality advance principles that differ in topic, scope, and assumptions. A typical version of the principle of utility maximization formulates a standard rather than a procedure for decisions, evaluates decisions comprehensively, and relies on idealizations. I generalize the principle by removing some idealizations and making adjustments for their absence. The generalizations accommodate agents who have incomplete probability and utility assignments and are imperfectly rational. …Read more
  •  6
    Contractiarianism and Bargaining Theory
    Journal of Philosophical Research 16 369-385. 1991.
    Classical bargaining theory attempts to solve a bargaining problem using only the information about the problem contained in the representation of its possible outcomes in utility space. However, this information usually underdetermines the solution. I use additional information about interpersonal comparisons of utility and bargaining power. The solution is then the outcome that maximizes the sum of power-weighted utilities. I use these results to advance a contractarian argument for a utilitar…Read more
  •  45
  •  22
    The Hypothesis of Nash Equilibrium and Its Bayesian Justification
    In Dag Prawitz & Dag Westerståhl (eds.), Logic and Philosophy of Science in Uppsala, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 245--264. 1994.
    How does Bayesian reasoning support participation in a game's Nash equilibrium? This paper provides an answer.
  •  177
    Expected utility and risk
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37 (4): 419-442. 1986.
    The rule to maximize expected utility is intended for decisions where options involve risk. In those decisions the decision maker's attitude toward risk is important, and the rule ought to take it into account. Allais's and Ellsberg's paradoxes, however, suggest that the rule ignores attitudes toward risk. This suggestion is supported by recent psychological studies of decisions. These studies present a great variety of cases where apparently rational people violate the rule because of aversion …Read more
  •  7
    Theory and evidence
    Philosophical Topics 12 (2): 294-299. 1981.
  •  16
    A Study of Concepts (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 48 (1): 159-160. 1994.
    Peacocke presents a theory of concepts that builds upon his earlier articles. He takes concepts as abstract objects that are components of thoughts, that are individuated by the test of informativeness, and whose possession affects a thinker's capacity for thought. His view is Fregean, but he individuates concepts more finely than Frege. For instance, he takes a first-level predicative concept as a mode of presentation of a property rather than as a function from objects to truth values.
  •  15
    Decisions to follow a rule
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25 (2): 280-281. 2002.
    Rachlin favors following patterns over making decisions case by case. However, his accounts of self-control and altruism do not establish the rationality of making decisions according to patterns. The best arguments for using patterns as a standard of evaluation appeal to savings in cognitive costs and compensation for irrational dispositions. What the arguments show depends on how they are elaborated and refined.
  •  20
    A bias of rationality
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 59 (1). 1981.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  35
    Groups of people perform acts that are subject to standards of rationality. A committee may sensibly award fellowships, or may irrationally award them in violation of its own policies. A theory of collective rationality defines collective acts that are evaluable for rationality and formulates principles for their evaluation. This book argues that a group's act is evaluable for rationality if it is the products of acts its members fully control. It also argues that such an act is collectively rat…Read more
  •  42
    Optimization and improvement (review)
    Philosophical Studies 148 (3). 2010.
    Agents face serious obstacles to making optimal decisions. For instance, their cognitive limits stand in the way. John Pollock’s book, Thinking about Acting , suggests many ways of revising decision principles to accommodate human limits and to direct limited, artificial agents. The book’s main proposal is to replace optimization, or expected-utility maximization, with locally global planning. This essay describes optimization and locally global planning, and then argues that optimization among …Read more
  • Joseph Y. Halpern, Reasoning about Uncertainty Reviewed by
    Philosophy in Review 24 (5): 333-336. 2004.
    This book review describes and evaluates Joseph Halpern's ideas about reasoning, in particular, reasoning involving conditions.
  •  7
    When new technologies create risks, government agencies use regulations to control the risks. This paper advances a method of evaluating a democracy’s regulation of risks. It assumes that a regulatory agency should act as the public would act in ideal conditions for negotiation if the public were rational and informed. The method relies on decision theory and game theory to ascertain whether a regulation has the public’s informed support. The Occupational Safety and Health Administration’s regul…Read more
  •  9
    This book represents a major contribution to game theory. It offers this conception of equilibrium in games: strategic equilibrium. This conception arises from a study of expected utility decision principles, which must be revised to take account of the evidence a choice provides concerning its outcome. The argument for these principles distinguishes reasons for action from incentives, and draws on contemporary analyses of counterfactual conditionals. The book also includes a procedure for ident…Read more
  •  325
    Hierarchical maximization of two kinds of expected utility
    Philosophy of Science 55 (4): 560-582. 1988.
    Causal decision theory produces decision instability in cases such as Death in Damascus where a decision itself provides evidence concerning the utility of options. Several authors have proposed ways of handling this instability. William Harper (1985 and 1986) advances one of the most elegant proposals. He recommends maximizing causal expected utility among the options that are causally ratifiable. Unfortunately, Harper's proposal imposes certain restrictions; for instance, the restriction that …Read more
  •  38
    Trustee decisions in investment and finance
    Journal of Business Ethics 7 (1-2). 1988.
    When a trustee makes a decision for a client, a standard objective is to decide as the client would if he had the trustee's information. How can this objective be attained when, given the trustee's information, there is still uncertainty about the consequences of alternative courses of action? A promising approach is to apply the rule to maximize expected utility using the client's utilities for consequences and the trustee's probabilities for states. But taking utilities and probabilities from …Read more
  •  8
    This book represents a major contribution to game theory. It offers this conception of equilibrium in games: strategic equilibrium. This conception arises from a study of expected utility decision principles, which must be revised to take account of the evidence a choice provides concerning its outcome. The argument for these principles distinguishes reasons for action from incentives, and draws on contemporary analyses of counterfactual conditionals. The book also includes a procedure for ident…Read more
  •  11
    Regulation of risks
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 (4): 564-565. 2005.
    Sunstein argues that heuristics misguide moral judgments. Principles that are normally sound falter in unusual cases. In particular, heuristics generate erroneous judgments about regulation of risks. Sunstein's map of moral reasoning omits some prominent contours. The simple heuristics he suggests neglect a reasoner's attempt to balance the pros and cons of regulating a risk.
  •  31
    I will characterize the utilitarian and maximin rules of social choice game-theoretically. That is, I will introduce games whose solutions are the utilitarian and maximin distributions respectively. Then I will compare the rules by exploring similarities and differences between these games. This method of comparison has been carried out by others. But I characterize the two rules using games that involve bargaining within power structures. This new characterization better highlights the ethical …Read more
  •  84
    Decision instability
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 63 (4). 1985.
    In some decision problems adoption of an option furnishes evidence about the option's consequences. Rational decisions take account of that evidence, although it makes an option's adoption changes the option's expected utility.
  • This collection treats classic problems in decision theory such as Newcomb's Problem and the Prisoner's Dilemma. The reviews describes and evaluates the essays.
  •  90
    Utility tempered with equality
    Noûs 17 (3): 423-439. 1983.
  •  60
    Calibration
    In Henk W. de Regt (ed.), Epsa Philosophy of Science: Amsterdam 2009, Springer. pp. 415--425. 2009.
    Abner Shimony argues that degrees of belief satisfy the axioms of probability because their epistemic goal is to match estimates of objective probabilities. Because the estimates obey the axioms of probability, degrees of belief must also obey them to reach their epistemic goal. This calibration argument meets some objections, but with a few revisions it can surmount those objections. It offers a good alternative to the Dutch book argument for compliance with the probability axioms. The defense …Read more
  •  31
    Mean-risk decision analysis
    Theory and Decision 23 (1): 89-111. 1987.
  •  12
    Conditionalization and Evidence
    Journal of Critical Analysis 8 (1): 15-18. 1979.
  •  11
    Intrinsic Utility’s Compositionality
    Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1 (3): 545--563. 2015.