•  40
    Risk as a Consequence
    Topoi 39 (2): 293-303. 2020.
    Expected-utility theory advances representation theorems that do not take the risk an act generates as a consequence of the act. However, a principle of expected-utility maximization that explains the rationality of preferences among acts must, for normative accuracy, take the act’s risk as a consequence of the act if the agent cares about the risk. I defend this conclusion against the charge that taking an act’s consequences to comprehend all the agent cares about trivializes the principle of e…Read more
  •  38
    Decision When Desires Are Uncertain
    Bowling Green Studies in Applied Philosophy 3 69-75. 1981.
    An agent in a decision problem may not know the goals that should guide selection of an option. Accommodating this ignorance require methods that supplement expected utility theory.
  •  38
    Trustee decisions in investment and finance
    Journal of Business Ethics 7 (1-2). 1988.
    When a trustee makes a decision for a client, a standard objective is to decide as the client would if he had the trustee's information. How can this objective be attained when, given the trustee's information, there is still uncertainty about the consequences of alternative courses of action? A promising approach is to apply the rule to maximize expected utility using the client's utilities for consequences and the trustee's probabilities for states. But taking utilities and probabilities from …Read more
  •  37
    Contractiarianism and Bargaining Theory
    Journal of Philosophical Research 16 369-385. 1991.
    Classical bargaining theory attempts to solve a bargaining problem using only the information about the problem contained in the representation of its possible outcomes in utility space. However, this information usually underdetermines the solution. I use additional information about interpersonal comparisons of utility and bargaining power. The solution is then the outcome that maximizes the sum of power-weighted utilities. I use these results to advance a contractarian argument for a utilitar…Read more
  •  35
    Auguste Comte, John Stuart Mill, et l'economie politique
    Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy 8 (1): 40-53. 1996.
    none.
  •  35
    Groups of people perform acts that are subject to standards of rationality. A committee may sensibly award fellowships, or may irrationally award them in violation of its own policies. A theory of collective rationality defines collective acts that are evaluable for rationality and formulates principles for their evaluation. This book argues that a group's act is evaluable for rationality if it is the products of acts its members fully control. It also argues that such an act is collectively rat…Read more
  •  34
    Decisions without Sharp Probabilities
    Philosophia Scientiae 19 213-225. 2015.
    Adam Elga [Elga 2010] argues that no principle of rationality leads from unsharp probabilities to decisions. He concludes that a perfectly rational agent does not have unsharp probabilities. This paper defends unsharp probabilities. It shows how unsharp probabilities may ground rational decisions
  •  34
    Rational Responses to Risks
    Oxford University Press. 2020.
    A philosophical account of risk, such as this book provides, states what risk is, which attitudes to it are rational, and which acts affecting risks are rational. Attention to the nature of risk reveals two types of risk, first, a chance of a bad event, and, second, an act’s risk in the sense of the volatility of its possible outcomes. The distinction is normatively significant because different general principles of rationality govern attitudes to these two types of risk. Rationality strictl…Read more
  •  33
    The contributors
    Synthese 176 (1): 149-150. 2010.
    This lists the contributors to a special issue on realistic standards for decisions.
  •  31
    I will characterize the utilitarian and maximin rules of social choice game-theoretically. That is, I will introduce games whose solutions are the utilitarian and maximin distributions respectively. Then I will compare the rules by exploring similarities and differences between these games. This method of comparison has been carried out by others. But I characterize the two rules using games that involve bargaining within power structures. This new characterization better highlights the ethical …Read more
  •  31
    Mean-risk decision analysis
    Theory and Decision 23 (1): 89-111. 1987.
  •  30
    Introduction
    Synthese 176 (1): 1-3. 2010.
    This introduction is to a special journal issue on realistic standards for decisions. A realistic standard takes account of human cognitive limits, the circumstances for making a decision, and the features of a decision problem.
  •  27
    Adam Morton on Dilemmas
    Dialogue 33 (1): 95. 1994.
    Adam Morton offers a novel approach to making decisions. This review describes and evaluates his innovations
  •  27
    Change in the Decision Sciences
    Lato Sensu: Revue de la Société de Philosophie des Sciences 5 (1): 13-19. 2018.
    A common type of change in science occurs as theorists generalize a model of a phenomenon by removing some idealizations of the model. This type of change occurs in the decision sciences and also in the normative branch of the decision sciences that treats rational choice. After presenting a general ac-count of model generalization, the paper illustrates generalization of models in normative decision theory. The principal illustration generalizes a standard model of rational choice by removing t…Read more
  •  25
    The Standard of Living
    Philosophical Books 29 (3): 180-183. 1988.
    This book review evaluate Amartya Sen's views about capabilities and the standard of living.
  •  25
    J. Howard Sobel has long been recognized as an important figure in philosophical discussions of rational decision. He has done much to help formulate the concept of causal decision theory. In this volume of essays Sobel explores the Bayesian idea that rational actions maximize expected values, where an action's expected value is a weighted average of its agent's values for its possible total outcomes. Newcomb's Problem and The Prisoner's Dilemma are discussed, and Allais-type puzzles are viewed …Read more
  •  25
    Coordination and Hyperrationality
    ProtoSociology 35 197-214. 2018.
    Margaret Gilbert (1990) argues that although the rationality of the agents in a standard coordination problem does not suffice for their coordination, a social convention of coordination, understood as the agents’ joint acceptance of a principle requiring their coordination, does the job. Gilbert’s argument targets agents rational in the game-theoretic sense, which following Sobel (1994: Chap. 14), I call hyperrational agents. I agree that hyperrational agents may fail to coordinate in some case…Read more
  •  24
    Decisions without Sharp Probabilities
    Philosophia Scientiae 19 213-225. 2015.
    Adam Elga [Elga 2010] argues that no principle of rationality leads from unsharp probabilities to decisions. He concludes that a perfectly rational agent does not have unsharp probabilities. This paper defends unsharp probabilities. It shows how unsharp probabilities may ground rational decisions.
  •  22
    Decisions in Dynamic Settings
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1986. 1986.
    In a decision problem with a dynamic setting there is at least one option whose realization would change the expected utilities of options by changing the probability or utility function with respect to which the expected utilities of options are computed. A familiar example is Newcomb's problem. William Harper proposes a generalization of causal decision theory intended to cover all decision problems with dynamic settings, not just Newcomb's problem. His generalization uses Richard Jeffrey's id…Read more
  •  22
    Auguste Comte: Trajectoires positivistes 1798–1998 (review)
    Isis 96 470-471. 2005.
    Auguste Comte's version of positivism shares logical positivism's aversion to metaphysics.
  •  22
  •  22
    The Hypothesis of Nash Equilibrium and Its Bayesian Justification
    In Dag Prawitz & Dag Westerståhl (eds.), Logic and Philosophy of Science in Uppsala, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 245--264. 1994.
    How does Bayesian reasoning support participation in a game's Nash equilibrium? This paper provides an answer.
  •  22
    Like many theorists before him, Paul Weirich has set out to find the Holy Grail of classical game theory: the solution concept that identifies the uniquely rational solution to every non-cooperative game. In this book, he reports an intermediate stage in his quest. He cannot actually identify the unique solution for every game but, he believes, he has found a new concept of equilibrium that is a necessary property of that solution.
  •  21
    From rationality to coordination
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (2): 179-180. 2003.
    Game theory's paradoxes stimulate the study of rationality. Sometimes they motivate the revising of standard principles of rationality. Other times they call for revising applications of those principles or introducing supplementary principles of rationality. I maintain that rationality adjusts its demands to circumstances, and in ideal games of coordination it yields a payoff-dominant equilibrium.
  •  21
    Liberal Utilitarianism
    Philosophical Books 30 (3): 182-183. 1989.
    This book review describes and evaluates Jonathan Riley's views about utilitarianism.
  •  20
    This book review describes and evaluates John Pollock's view about rational decision-making.
  •  20
    A bias of rationality
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 59 (1). 1981.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  19
    Value in Ethics and Economics (review)
    Philosophical Books 36 (2): 139-141. 1995.
    This review describes and evaluates a book by Elizabeth Anderson.