Brown University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1982
Notre Dame, Indiana, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
Epistemology
Metaphilosophy
Meta-Ethics
  •  21
    Resurrecting Old-Fashioned Foundationalism (edited book)
    Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. 2000.
    The contributions in this volume make an important effort to resurrect a rather old fashioned form of foundationalism. They defend the position that there are some beliefs that are justified, and are not themselves justified by any further beliefs. This epistemic foundationalism has been the subject of rigorous attack by a wide range of theorists in recent years, leading to the impression that foundationalism is a thing of the past. DePaul argues that it is precisely the volume and virulence of …Read more
  •  102
    Liberal exclusions and foundationalism
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 1 (1): 103-120. 1998.
    Certain versions of liberalism exclude from public political discussions the reasons some citizens regard as most fundamental, reasons having to do with their deepest religious, philosophical, moral or political views. This liberal exclusion of deep and deeply held reasons from political discussions has been controversial. In this article I will point out a way in which the discussion seems to presuppose a foundationalist conception of human reasoning. This is rather surprising, inasmuch as one …Read more
  •  256
    Naivete and corruption in moral inquiry
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48 (4): 619-635. 1988.
  •  86
    Character Traits, Virtues, and Vices
    The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 9 141-157. 2000.
    Recently, Gilbert Harman has used empirical results obtained by social psychologists to argue that there are no character traits of the type presupposed by virtue ethics—no honesty or dishonesty, no courage or cowardice, in short, no virtue or vice. In this paper, I critically assess his argument as well as that of the social psychologists he appeals to. I suggest that the experimental results recounted by Harman would not much concern such classical virtue theorists as Plato—particularly the Pl…Read more
  •  12
    Comments on Two of Depaul’s Puzzles
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (3): 636-639. 2002.
    I’m not sure one even needs to think a state of affairs is true for us to take attitudinal pleasure in it. We surely take pleasure in imagining states of affairs. In such a case, we are well aware that the state of affairs that is the object of our enjoyment does not obtain. What is the proper account of the pleasure we take from imagining? I am fairly sure this is not a type of sensory pleasure. Would it make sense to say that what S is attitudinally pleased by is the state of affairs consistin…Read more
  •  4
    Ugly Analyses and Value
    In Adrian Haddock, Alan Millar & Duncan Pritchard (eds.), Epistemic value, Oxford University Press. 2009.
  •  110
    Supervenience and moral dependence
    Philosophical Studies 51 (3). 1987.
    One aim philosophers have in constructing moral theories is to identify the natural or non-Moral characteristics that make actions right or obligatory, Things good, Or persons virtuous. Yet we have no clear understanding of what it is for certain of a thing's non-Moral properties to be responsible for its moral properties. Given the recent interest in the concept of supervenience one might think that the dependence of moral on natural properties could be explained in terms of it. Unfortunately, …Read more
  •  42
    Brink's Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (3): 731-735. 1993.
  • Coherentism
    In Robert Audi (ed.), The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, Cambridge University Press. 1995.
  •  125
    Pyrrhonian moral skepticism and the problem of the criterion
    Philosophical Issues 19 (1): 38-56. 2009.
    No Abstract
  •  86
    Intuitions in moral inquiry
    In David Copp (ed.), The Oxford handbook of ethical theory, Oxford University Press. pp. 595--623. 2006.
    This chapter begins with a weak understanding of intuitions as beliefs that do not result from more familiar sources, but that the person currently holds simply because the proposition believed seems true to the person upon due consideration. Nearly all moral inquiry makes significant use of moral intuitions. Reflective equilibrium is perhaps the most sophisticated intuitionistic approach to moral inquiry. It modifies the usual understanding of reflective equilibrium by arguing that inquirers mu…Read more
  •  21
    We all have moral beliefs. But what if one beleif conflicts with another? DePaul argues that we have to make our beliefs cohere, but that the current coherence methods are seriously flawed. It is not just the arguments that need to be considered in moral enquiry. DePaul asserts that the ability to make sensitive moral judgements is vital to any philosophical inquiry into morality. The inquirer must consider how her life experiences and experiences with literature, film and theatre have influence…Read more
  •  76
    Sosa, Certainty and the Problem of the Criterion
    Philosophical Papers 40 (3): 287-304. 2011.
    Abstract In Reflective Knowledge, Ernest Sosa continues his detailed and intriguing defense of his two level account of knowledge that recognizes both animal and reflective knowledge. The latter more impressive type of knowledge requires a coherent positive epistemic perspective defending the reliability of a source of belief. Viewing Sosa's discussion from the through the lens provided by R.M. Chisholm's treatments of the problem of the criterion, I worry that Sosa's approach is too far in the …Read more
  •  18
    Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (3): 731-735. 1993.