• Foundation of Ethics
    with Leroy S. Rouner and Stanley Hauerwas
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 16 (2): 178-181. 1984.
  •  7
    Naming Evil, Judging Evil
    University of Chicago Press. 2006.
    Is it more dangerous to call something evil or not to? This fundamental question deeply divides those who fear that the term oversimplifies grave problems and those who worry that, to effectively address such issues as terrorism and genocide, we must first acknowledge them as evil. Recognizing that the way we approach this dilemma can significantly affect both the harm we suffer and the suffering we inflict, a distinguished group of contributors engages in the debate with this series of timely a…Read more
  •  52
    Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity by Richard Rorty (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 87 (12): 708-711. 1990.
  •  29
    3 Regulation: A Substitute for Morality
    Hastings Center Report 10 (1): 31-33. 1980.
  •  23
    Freedom and Immortality
    with I. T. Ramsey
    Philosophical Quarterly 13 (51): 182. 1963.
  • Whose Justice? Which Rationality?
    Journal of Religious Ethics 16 (2): 363-363. 1988.
  •  8
    The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy
    Philosophical Books 37 (3): 183-186. 1996.
  • Morality and Modernity (review)
    Radical Philosophy 60. 1992.
  •  32
    38. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory
    In Bernard Williams (ed.), Essays and Reviews: 1959-2002, Princeton University Press. pp. 184-186. 2014.
  •  6
  •  52
    Vi. after virtue and marxism: A response to Wartofsky
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 27 (1-4). 1984.
    My response to Wartofsky's questions concerning why the Aristotelian tradition of the virtues was rejected and why individualist modes of thought found such ready acceptance is to sketch the kind of historical narrative which I take it must be written if his questions are to be adequately answered. I identify one source of difference between us in the varying extent to which he and I have rejected Marxist modes of thought
  • Tolerancja i dobra konfliktu
    Studia Philosophica Wratislaviensia 111-114. 2009.
  • Après la vertu, coll. « Léviathan »
    Les Etudes Philosophiques 4 (1): 565-567. 1999.
  •  4
    Reviews (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 18 (4): 344-345. 1968.
  • Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues
    Philosophical Quarterly 51 (203): 266-269. 2001.
  •  1
    The Tasks of Philosophy: Volume 1: Selected Essays
    Cambridge University Press. 2006.
    How should we respond when some of our basic beliefs are put into question? What makes a human body distinctively human? Why is truth an important good? These are among the questions explored in this 2006 collection of essays by Alasdair MacIntyre, one of the most creative and influential philosophers working today. Ten of MacIntyre's most influential essays written over almost thirty years are collected together here for the first time. They range over such topics as the issues raised by differ…Read more
  •  227
    Social structures and their threats to moral agency
    Philosophy 74 (3): 311-329. 1999.
    Imagine first the case of J (who might be anybody, jemand). J used to inhabit a social order, or rather an area within a social order, where socially approved roles were unusually well-defined. Responsibilities were allocated to each such role and each sphere of role-structured activity was clearly demarcated. These allocations and demarcations were embodied in and partly constituted by the expectations that others had learned to have of those who occupied each such role. For those who occupied …Read more
  •  81
    Philosophical Education Against Contemporary Culture
    Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 87 43-56. 2013.
    Four stages in an adequate philosophical education are distinguished. The first is that in which students learn to put in question some commonly shared assumptions about what happiness is and to ask what the good of engaging in this kind of questioning is. The second is a conceptual and linguistic analysis of “good” which enables questions about what human goods are to be formulated. The third is an investigation into the nature and unity of human beings designed to enable us to propose rational…Read more
  •  1
    Spinoza
    In Paul Edwards (ed.), The Encyclopedia of philosophy, Macmillan. 1967.
  •  2
    How can we Learn what Veritatis Splendor has to Teach?
    The Thomist 58 (2): 171-195. 1994.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:HOW CAN WE LEARN WHAT VER/TATIS SPLENDOR HAS TO TEACH? ALASDAIR MAclNTYRE University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana V-ERITATIS SPLENDOR can be read in two very different ways. It can be read, and of course it should be ad, as a papal encyclical, a piece of authoritative Christian teaching. As such, it is addressed to the Catholic bishops and its subject-matter is not only Christian moral teaching in general, but more particularly …Read more
  • Metaphysical Beliefs: Three Essays
    with Stephen Toulmin, Ronald W. Hepburn, and Michael B. Foster
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 10 (37): 73-78. 1959.
  •  3
    Objectivity in Morality and Objectivity in Science
    In H. Tristram Englehardt, Jr & Daniel Callahan (eds.), Morals, Science and Sociality, Hastings Center. pp. 21-39. 1978.
  •  184
    Does Applied Ethics Rest on a Mistake?
    The Monist 67 (4): 498-513. 1984.
    ‘Applied ethics’, as that expression is now used, is a single rubric for a large range of different theoretical and practical activities. Such rubrics function partly as a protective device both within the academic community and outside it; a name of this kind suggests not just a discipline, but a particular type of discipline. In the case of ‘applied ethics’ the suggestive power of the name derives from a particular conception of the relationship of ethics to what goes on under the rubric of ‘a…Read more
  •  42
  •  11
    Presents MacIntyre's most explicit defense of his approach to Thomistic metaphysics. This lecture follows MacIntyre's argument in After Virtue that modern philosophy has very literally lost its way, and the problems it faces are insoluble. The difficulties are twofold, and stem from the Cartesian turn to the self in the XVith century.