•  380
    Toward a theory of medical fallibility
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 1 (1): 13-23. 1976.
  •  56
    Imperatives, reasons for action, and morals
    Journal of Philosophy 62 (19): 513-524. 1965.
  •  20
    The Revisions series marks an attempt to recover what is viable in the traditions of which we ought to be the heirs without ignoring what it was that made those traditions vulnerable to modernity.
  •  14
    Philosophy: Past Conflict and Future Direction
    Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 61 (1). 1987.
  •  9
    Richard Rorty argues that the present state of analytic philosophy is the result of the collapse of the logical empiricist program. But most of the characteristics of analytic philosophy which Rorty ascribes to that collapse predated logical empiricism. The historical explanation of the present state of philosophy must begin not later than with the schism between philosophy and the other disciplines in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. To begin then leads to a different view of how philo…Read more
  •  54
    This new edition includes a substantial new preface by the author, in which he discusses repression, determinism, transference, and "practical rationality," and ...
  • Sporne koncepcje sprawiedliwości i racjonalności
    Studia Philosophica Wratislaviensia 169-184. 2007.
  •  10
    Historical materialism: The method, the theories
    Philosophical Books 2 (4): 24-24. 1961.
  •  21
    Purpose and Intelligent Action
    with P. H. Nowell-Smith
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 34 (1): 79-112. 1960.
  •  98
    The Savage Mind
    with Claude Levi-Strauss
    Philosophical Quarterly 17 (69): 372. 1967.
    "Every word, like a sacred object, has its place. No _précis_ is possible. This extraordinary book must be read."—Edmund Carpenter, _New York Times Book Review _ "No outline is possible; I can only say that reading this book is a most exciting intellectual exercise in which dialectic, wit, and imagination combine to stimulate and provoke at every page."—Edmund Leach, _Man _ "Lévi-Strauss's books are tough: very scholarly, very dense, very rapid in argument. But once you have mastered him, human …Read more
  •  59
    Richard Rorty (1931 – 2007)
    Common Knowledge 14 (2): 183-192. 2008.
  •  4
    Review of Ernest Gellner: Legitimation of Belief (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 29 (1): 105-110. 1978.
  •  7
    Naming Evil, Judging Evil
    University of Chicago Press. 2006.
    Is it more dangerous to call something evil or not to? This fundamental question deeply divides those who fear that the term oversimplifies grave problems and those who worry that, to effectively address such issues as terrorism and genocide, we must first acknowledge them as evil. Recognizing that the way we approach this dilemma can significantly affect both the harm we suffer and the suffering we inflict, a distinguished group of contributors engages in the debate with this series of timely a…Read more
  •  52
    Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity by Richard Rorty (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 87 (12): 708-711. 1990.
  •  29
    3 Regulation: A Substitute for Morality
    Hastings Center Report 10 (1): 31-33. 1980.
  •  21
    Freedom and Immortality
    with I. T. Ramsey
    Philosophical Quarterly 13 (51): 182. 1963.
  •  62
  •  8
    The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy
    Philosophical Books 37 (3): 183-186. 1996.
  • Morality and Modernity (review)
    Radical Philosophy 60. 1992.
  •  31
    38. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory
    In Bernard Williams (ed.), Essays and Reviews: 1959-2002, Princeton University Press. pp. 184-186. 2014.
  •  5
  • Whose Justice? Which Rationality?
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 18 (4): 388-404. 1988.
  • Tolerancja i dobra konfliktu
    Studia Philosophica Wratislaviensia 111-114. 2009.
  • Après la vertu, coll. « Léviathan »
    Les Etudes Philosophiques 4 (1): 565-567. 1999.
  •  4
    Reviews (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 18 (4): 344-345. 1968.
  • Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues
    Philosophical Quarterly 51 (203): 266-269. 2001.
  •  220
    Social structures and their threats to moral agency
    Philosophy 74 (3): 311-329. 1999.
    Imagine first the case of J (who might be anybody, jemand). J used to inhabit a social order, or rather an area within a social order, where socially approved roles were unusually well-defined. Responsibilities were allocated to each such role and each sphere of role-structured activity was clearly demarcated. These allocations and demarcations were embodied in and partly constituted by the expectations that others had learned to have of those who occupied each such role. For those who occupied …Read more