•  53
    Kant's Empiricism
    Review of Metaphysics 50 (3). 1997.
    It might seem inappropriate to describe Kant as an empiricist. He believed, contrary to the basic empiricist principle, that there are nontrivial propositions that can be known independently of experience. He devoted virtually all of his efforts as a researcher to discovering how it is possible for us to have this "synthetic a priori" knowledge. However, Kant also believed that there are some things that we can know only through sensory experience. Though he did not give these empirical proposit…Read more
  •  39
    Reid and Smith on Vision
    Journal of Scottish Philosophy 2 (2): 103-118. 2004.
    Reid's Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense devotes more space to double vision than to any other topic. In what follows, I examine why this subject was so important to Reid and why he dealt with it as he did. I also consider whether his argument for his position begs the question against his main opponents, Berkeley and Robert Smith. I show that, as Reid presented it, it does, but that he could have said more than he did in reply to Smith. My discussion of why double vi…Read more
  •  44
    Nativism and the Nature of Thought in Reid's Account of Our Knowledge of the External World
    In Terence Cuneo Rene van Woudenberg (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Thomas Reid, Cambridge University Press. pp. 156--179. 2004.
    This is a wide ranging survey of the extent and nature of Reid's nativist commitments and of their implications for his account of perception and his realism.
  •  114
    Kant’s Account of Sensation
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 20 (1): 63-88. 1990.
    Kant defined ‘sensation’as ‘the effect of an object on the representative capacity, so far as we are affected by it.’ This is, to put it mildly, not one among his more elegant, clear or helpful sayings. And it is merely an instance of a more general malaise. Kant did not say as much about sensation as he should have, and his account-or lack of it-can be seen at the root of many of the difficulties that have plagued his readers.
  •  25
    Kant’s First Argument in the Metaphysical Expositions
    Proceedings of the Sixth International Kant Congress 2 (1): 219-227. 1989.
    This paper argues that Kant's first argument in the metaphysical expositions defends a foundational insight on which much of the rest of his thought depends: that our experience of the spatial properties and relations of things is not based on comparison of the things (matters) found in space or on any form of reasoning (causal or demonstrative). Spatial and temporal relations are originally given in sensory intuition, not constructed or inferred.
  •  20
    Reid's Critique of Berkely's Position on the Inverted Image
    Journal of Scottish Philosophy 16 (2): 175-191. 2018.
    (Originally published in _Reid Studies_ 4 (2000-01): 35-51.) Reid and Berkeley disagreed over whether we directly perceive objects located outside of us in a surrounding space, commonly revealed by both vision and touch. Berkeley considered a successful account of erect vision to be crucial for deciding this dispute, at one point calling it ‘the principal point in the whole optic theory.’ Reid's critique of Berkeley's position on this topic is very brief, and appears to miss Berkeley's point. I …Read more
  •  9
    This book presents a paragraph-by-paragraph analysis of all of the major arguments and explanations in the "aesthetic" of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. The first part of the book aims to provide a clear analysis of the meanings of the terms Kant uses to name faculties and types of representation, the second offers a thorough account of the reasoning behind the "metaphysical" and "transcendental" expositions, and the third investigates the basis for Kant's major conclusions about space, time, a…Read more
  •  83
    Kant’s Account of Intuition
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21 (2): 165-193. 1991.
    This paper outlines the history of the distinction between a higher and a lower cognitive function up to Kant. It is argued that Kant initially drew the distinction in Scholastic terms--as a distinction between a capacity to image particulars and a capacity to represent universals. However, features of his project in the Critique led him to reformulate the distinction in terms of immediacy and mediacy. Nonetheless, for certain purposes the older, Scholastic distinction retained its attractivenes…Read more
  •  46
    Drawing on work done by Helmholtz, I argue that Reid was in no position to infer that objects appear as if projected on the inner surface of a sphere, or that they have the geometric properties of such projections even though they do not look concave towards the eye. A careful consideration of the phenomena of visual experience, as further illuminated by the practice of visual artists, should have led him to conclude that the sides of visible appearances either look straight, in which case their…Read more
  •  74
    In section 12 of the Dialogues, Hume claimed, without reference, that Seneca had written that to know God is to worship him. His source has proven hard to find. This note identifies some possibilities and argues in favour of one of them—one that has not been recognized by recent editors of the Dialogues.
  •  50
    Reid's response to Hume's perceptual relativity argument
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1): 25-49. 2011.
    Reid declared Hume's appeal to variation in the magnitude of a table with distance to be the best argument that had ever been offered for the ‘ideal hypothesis’ that we experience nothing but our own mental states. Reid's principal objection to this argument fails to apply to minimally visible points. He did establish that we have reason to take our perceptions to be caused by external objects. But his case that we directly perceive external objects is undermined by what Hume had to say about th…Read more
  •  116
    Hume's scepticism about the ability of demonstrative reasoning to justify many of our most common and important beliefs, such those concerning the connection between causes and effects, does not sit well with his tendency to make normative claims about which beliefs we ought to accept. I argue that Hume's naturalist account of the causes of belief is nonetheless rich enough to provide for normative assessments of belief and even for the modification of beliefs in light of these assessments. I ar…Read more
  •  95
    Intuition and construction in Berkeley's account of visual space
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 32 (1): 63-84. 1994.
    This paper examines Berkeley's attitude toward our perception of spatial relations on the two- dimensional visual field. This is a topic on which there has been some controversy. Historians of visual theory have tended to suppose that Berkeley took "all" spatial relations to be derived in the way our knowledge of depth is: from association of more primitive sensations which are themselves in no way spatial. But many philosophers commenting on Berkeley have supposed that he takes our awareness of…Read more
  •  123
    Kant, Mendelssohn, Lambert, and the subjectivity of time
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 29 (2): 227-251. 1991.
    On the basis of an examination of Kant's correspondence with Mendelssohn, 1766-1770, I argue that already in 1770 Kant had before him a decisive refutation of the view that time is imposed by the mind on its representations, and that Kant did not hold any such view of the subjectivity of time in his later work. Kant's mature view is that time is subjective only in the sense that it is the manner in which the empirically observable subject receives sensory matter, not in the sense that the subjec…Read more
  •  33
    Anthony Quinton has argued that the trouble with Kant is that he does not take empirical experience to have any significant role to play in our knowledge of the world, and as a result is forced to take the imposition of a priori forms and categories to be arbitrary and unguided. While Quinton has pointed to a serious short-coming with those more rationalistic interpretations of Kant that would ascribe a dominant role to the understanding or the imagination in constituting experience, I make a ca…Read more
  •  88
    Is perceptual space monadic?
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 49 (June): 709-713. 1989.
    Against the claims of Russell, Goodman, and Albert Casullo, this paper argues that the location of phenomena in visual space cannot be determined through reference to monadic local properties of the visual field.
  •  87
    Reading Hume on Human Understanding (review)
    Hume Studies 30 (1): 183-187. 2004.
    Peter Millican’s Reading Hume on Human Understanding is a comprehensive overview of the philosophy of the first Enquiry and of the secondary literature on that work. As Millican notes, the first Enquiry has standardly been received as “a watered-down version of Book I of the Treatise, a more elegant and less taxing easy-read edition for the general public, with the technical details omitted and a few controversial sections on religion added to whet their appetite and provoke the ‘zealots’”. To t…Read more
  •  97
    Reid’s Account of Localization
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (2): 305-328. 2000.
    This paper contrasts three different positions taken by 18th century British scholars on how sensations, particularly sensations of colour and touch, come to be localized in space: Berkeley’s view that we learn to localize ideas of colour by associating certain purely qualitative features of those ideas with ideas of touch and motion, Hume’s view that visual and tangible impressions are originally disposed in space, and Reid’s view that we are innately disposed to refer appearances of colour to …Read more
  •  107
    Hume on Manners of Disposition and the Ideas of Space and Time
    Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 79 (2): 179-201. 1997.
    Scholars have almost universally agreed that Hume's account of space and time as manners of disposition of impressions is inconsistent with one of the most fundamental tenets of his empiricism: the thesis that all ideas are derived from simple impressions. This paper challenges that view and argues that Hume's position on the origin of our ideas of space and time is a profound, original, virtually unique, and even courageous approach to the problem of original space and time cognition, and a the…Read more
  •  45
    Hume and Reid on the Perception of Hardness
    Hume Studies 28 (1): 27-48. 2002.
    This paper considers an objection to the Humean view that perception involves introspective acquaintance with representative images. The objection, originally raised by Thomas Reid and recently endorsed by Nicholas Wolterstorff, states that no representative image can be hard, and concludes that acquaintance with such images cannot therefore account for our perception of hardness. I argue in response that a case has not been made for denying that representative images can be hard. Hardness, as u…Read more
  •  62
    Berkeley's Argument for Other Minds
    History of Philosophy Quarterly 7 (4). 1990.
    The literature on Berkeley is almost unanimous in taking this claim to know the existence of other finite spirits to rest on an argument from analogy. I show that this is not so and that Berkeley uses a causal argument to prove that there are other minds. Questions of the degree to which it is legitimate for Berkeley to appeal to causes, particularly occasional causes, are addressed in the process.
  •  86
    Hume’s Finite Geometry: A Reply to Mark Pressman
    Hume Studies 26 (1): 183-185. 2000.
    In “Hume on Geometry and Infinite Divisibility in the Treatise”, H. Mark Pressman charges that “the geometry Hume presents in the Treatise faces a serious set of problems”. This may well be; however, at least one of the charges Pressman levels against Hume invokes a false dichotomy, and a second rests on a non sequitur.
  •  43
    Dualism And The Experimentum Crucis
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 93 (1): 212-217. 2016.
    This book symposium contribution focuses on James Van Cleve's assertion that Reid's dualistic commitments are not essential to his other doctrines. I argue to the contrary that his critique of what he called the philosophy of ideas depends on a tacit assumption of dualism.
  •  34
    Hume’s Reason (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67 (1): 233-236. 2003.
    In this significant contribution to the history of logic and exemplary work of contextual exegesis, David Owen shows that the early modern conception of reasoning was radically different from our own and applies this insight to the interpretation of Hume. We take the conclusions of deductive arguments to be entailed by premises in virtue of the form of those arguments. But early modern philosophers had a non-formal view of reasoning, dictated by the “way of ideas.” Owen maintains that we must re…Read more
  • This paper examines the principal objections that Hume’s Scots contemporaries, George Campbell, James Beattie, and Thomas Reid raised against his views of testimony, belief, and the “theory of ideas.” In opposition to Kant’s claim that “Reid, Oswald, and Beattie” had “appealed to common sense as an oracle when insight and research [failed them]” and had “[taken] for granted what [Hume] meant to call into doubt while emphatically, and often with great indignation, demonstrating what he had never …Read more
  •  4
    Classical Empiricism
    In Heather Dyke & Adrian Bardon (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Time, Wiley. 2013.
    This chapter on classical empiricism is divided into three sections, namely, absolutism, idealism, and memory. Presentism poses a particular problem for the empiricist view that the idea of time arises from people's experience of the succession of their ideas. The view that time passes independently of the succession of ideas was shared by canonically empiricist philosophers, such as Gassendi, Locke, and Newton. The idea of time arises from a compound impression that consists of successively dis…Read more
  •  325
    Hume's answer to Kant
    Noûs 32 (3): 331-360. 1998.
    Reid's Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense devotes more space to double vision than to any other topic. In what follows, I examine why this subject was so important to Reid and why he dealt with it as he did. I also consider whether his argument for his position begs the question against his main opponents, Berkeley and Robert Smith. I show that, as Reid presented it, it does, but that he could have said more than he did in reply to Smith. My discussion of why double vi…Read more
  •  98
    Condillac's paradox
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 43 (4): 403-435. 2005.
    : I argue that Condillac was committed to four mutually inconsistent propositions: that the mind is unextended, that sensations are modifications of the mind, that colours are sensations, and that colours are extended. I argue that this inconsistency was not just the blunder of a second-rate philosopher, but the consequence of a deep-seated tension in the views of early modern philosophers on the nature of the mind, sensation, and secondary qualities and that more widely studied figures, notably…Read more