University of Texas at Austin
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1975
Santa Clara, California, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
Ancient Greek and Roman Philosophy
Areas of Interest
Metaphysics
Normative Ethics
  •  12
    Compassion
    Philosophy and Theology 2 (2): 173-191. 1987.
    In the first part of this paper, I argue that the sentiment of compassion is a factor of the first importance in moral theory. This sentiment, which causes us to act well toward persons in need, is an essential element in the psychology of the morally well-developed person. Moral rationalists such as Epictetus and Kant, who contend that the source of moral value is reason rather than compassion, produce a distorted picture of our moral lives. Hume’s moral psychology gives compassion the place it…Read more
  •  25
    The Dialectic of Essence: A Study of Plato's Metaphysics (review) (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 42 (1): 97-98. 2004.
    This is a brief review of Silverman's study of Plato's ontology, in particular his theory of Forms. Silverman writes from an analytic viewpoint. He accepts the developmentalist picture of Plato's thought, but holds that the development is gradual. He focuses on the issue of predication, and especially self-predication. He tends to treat Plato's ontology as a free-standing subject. All of these features are controversial. I wondered in particular whether the analytic approach required more precis…Read more
  •  37
    Thomson on the moral specification of rights
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (4): 837-845. 1996.
  •  2
    Studies of Plato’s metaphysics have tended to emphasise either the radical change between the early Theory of Forms and the late doctrines of the Timaeus and the Sophist, or to insist on a unity of approach that is unchanged throughout Plato’s career. The author lays out an alternative approach. Focussing on two metaphysical doctrines of central importance to Plato’s thought – the Theory of Forms and the doctrine of Being and Becoming – he suggests a continuous progress can be traced through Pla…Read more
  •  6
    Scholars often assume that when Plato said that Forms are paradeigmata he meant that they were exemplars of the property they represent. I argue that "paradeigma" is better read as "pattern" than "exemplar." This reading is compatible with Plato's use of the term in all passages except Parm. 132d, where Parmenides misinterprets the term to make the theory of Forms susceptible to the Third Man Argument.
  •  41
    Richard D. Mohr, "The Platonic Cosmology" (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 25 (4): 585. 1987.
  •  15
    Plato's Analysis of Being and Not‐Being in the Sophist
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 18 (2): 199-211. 1980.
  •  69
    Why Did Plato Write Socratic Dialogues?
    Apeiron 30 (4). 1997.
    I argue that it was not Plato's intention in his Socratic dialogues to provide a biography of Socrates. Rather, his intention was to describe and defend the philosophical life against its critics. The Socratic dialogues are "unhappy encounters" between Socrates, defender of the life of philosophy, and those who do not comprehend or who reject that life.
  •  13
    The Historicity of Plato’s Apology
    Polis 18 (1-2): 41-57. 2001.
    Scholars who seek in Plato's early dialogues an accurate account of the philosophy of the historical Socrates place special weight on the Apology as a source of historical information about him. Even scholars like Charles Kahn, who generally reject this historicist approach to the early dialogues, accept the Apology as a ‘quasi-historical’ document. In this paper I attempt to raise doubts about the historical reliability of the Apology. I argue that the claims used to support the historicity of …Read more
  •  1
    Socratic metaphysics
    In John Bussanich & Nicholas D. Smith (eds.), The Bloomsbury companion to Socrates, Continuum. pp. 68-93. 2013.
    In this article I argue (against the views of Russell Dancy and Gregory Vlastos, but in support of the views of R. E. Allen, Gail Fine, and Francesco Fronterotta) that Euthyphro 5c-d and 6d-e show that Socrates had a metaphysics, early version of the theory of forms. I disagree with Fronterotta only on the separation of the forms in the Euthyphro.
  •  33
    Platonic Writings, Platonic Readings (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 13 (2): 173-175. 1990.
  •  105
    Eudaimonism and virtue
    Journal of Value Inquiry 35 (3): 325-342. 2001.
  •  26
    Thomson on the Moral Specification of Rights
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (4): 837-845. 1996.
  •  165
    Originally published in 1991, this book focuses on the concept of virtue, and in particular on the virtue of wisdom or knowledge, as it is found in the epic poems of Homer, some tragedies of Sophocles, selected writings of Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoic and Epicurean philosophers. The key questions discussed are the nature of the virtues, their relation to each other, and the relation between the virtues and happiness or well-being. This book provides the background and interpretative framework…Read more
  •  357
    In this paper I argue against the view of G.E.L. Owen that the second version of the Third Man Argument is a sound objection to Plato's conception of Forms as paradigms and that Plato knew it. The argument can be formulated so as to be valid, but Plato need not be committed to one of its premises. Forms are self-predicative, but the ground of self-predication is not the same as that of ordinary predication.
  •  43
    Book notes (review)
    with Ed L. Miller, Malcolm Jack, and Rolf George
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 17 (3): 369-370. 1979.
  •  42
    Zeno’s First Argument Concerning Plurality
    Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 60 (3): 247-256. 1978.
  •  38
    The Oxford Handbook to Plato (review)
    Ancient Philosophy 31 (1): 213-217. 2011.