•  5
    ``Rejoinder to Hasker"
    Faith and Philosophy 10 (2): 256-260. 1993.
  •  1744
    The Search for the Source of Epistemic Good
    Metaphilosophy 34 (1-2): 12-28. 2003.
    Knowledge has almost always been treated as good, better than mere true belief, but it is remarkably difficult to explain what it is about knowledge that makes it better. I call this “the value problem.” I have previously argued that most forms of reliabilism cannot handle the value problem. In this article I argue that the value problem is more general than a problem for reliabilism, infecting a host of different theories, including some that are internalist. An additional problem is that not a…Read more
  •  188
    Intellectual autonomy
    Philosophical Issues 23 (1): 244-261. 2013.
  •  190
    Religious Luck
    Faith and Philosophy 11 (3): 397-413. 1994.
  •  3755
    Exemplarist virtue theory
    Metaphilosophy 41 (1-2): 41-57. 1996.
    Abstract: In this essay I outline a radical kind of virtue theory I call exemplarism, which is foundational in structure but which is grounded in exemplars of moral goodness, direct reference to which anchors all the moral concepts in the theory. I compare several different kinds of moral theory by the way they relate the concepts of the good, a right act, and a virtue. In the theory I propose, these concepts, along with the concepts of a duty and of a good life, are defined by reference to exem…Read more
  •  23
    Przedwiedza a wolna wola
    Roczniki Filozoficzne 56 (2): 465-490. 2008.
  •  26
    Virtue in Ethics and Epistemology
    Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 71 1-17. 1997.
  •  2484
    Epistemic Authority and Its Critics
    European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 6 (4): 169--187. 2014.
  •  305
    Omnisubjectivity
    In L. Kvanvig Jonathan (ed.), Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion, Oxford University Press. pp. 231-248. 2013.
  •  567
    The Moral Gap (review)
    Philosophical Review 108 (2): 291-293. 1999.
    The title of Hare’s book refers to the gap between the demand that morality places on us and our natural capacity to live by it. Such a gap is paradoxical if we accept the “‘ought’ implies ‘can”’ principle. The solution, Hare argues, is that the gap is filled by the Christian God. So we ought to be moral and can do so—with divine assistance. Hare’s statement and defense of the existence of the gap combines a rigorously Kantian notion of the moral demand with a rigorously Calvinist notion of huma…Read more
  •  84
    Christian Monotheism
    Faith and Philosophy 6 (1): 3-18. 1989.
    In this paper I present an argument that there can be no more than one God in a way which allows me to give the doctrine ofthe Trinity logical priority over the attributes traditionally used in arguments for God’s unicity. The argument that there is at most one God makes no assumptions about the particular attributes included in divinity. It uses only the Identity of Indiscemibles and a Principle of Plenitude. I then offer a theory on the relationship between individuals and kinds which allows m…Read more
  •  6
    Intellectual motivation and the good of truth
    In Linda Zagzebski & Michael DePaul (eds.), Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives From Ethics and Epistemology, Oxford University Press. pp. 135--154. 2003.
  •  42
    Anselmian Explorations (review)
    American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 64 (2): 279-284. 1990.
  •  20
    Review: Responses (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (1). 2000.
  •  256
    Virtue Epistemology is a new movement receiving the bulk of recent attention from top epistemologists and ethicists; this volume reflects the best work in that vein. Included are unpublished articles by such eminent philosophers as Robert Audi, Simon Blackburn, Alvin Goldman, Christopher Hookway, Keith Lehrer, and Ernest Sosa
  •  690
    First Person and Third Person Reasons and Religious Epistemology
    European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 3 (2). 2011.
    In this paper I argue that there are two kinds of epistemic reasons. One kind is irreducibly first personal -- what I call deliberative reasons. The other kind is third personal -- what I call theoretical reasons. I argue that attending to this distinction illuminates a host of problems in epistemology in general and in religious epistemology in particular. These problems include (a) the way religious experience operates as a reason for religious belief, (b) how we ought to understand religious …Read more
  •  41
    Rational Faith: Catholic Responses to Reformed Epistemology (edited book)
    Notre Dame Press. 1993.
    Rational Faith contains nine new essays by Catholic philosophers who critically evaluate the recent work of the Reformed epistemologists, including Alvin Plantinga, Nicholas Wolterstorff and George Mavrodes. Although the contributors employ a distinctly Catholic perspective, their papers are by no means wholly polemical; instead, each reflects an appreciation of the importance of Reformed epistemology and its impact on contemporary religious philosophy.
  •  9
    What if the impossible had been actual
    In M. Beaty (ed.), Christian Theism and the Problems of Philosophy, University of Notre Dame Press. pp. 165--183. 1990.
  •  1
    Epistemic self-trust and the consensus gentium argument
    In Kelly James Clark & Raymond J. VanArragon (eds.), Evidence and Religious Belief, Oxford University Press. 2011.
  •  115
    The Virtues of God and the Foundations of Ethics
    Faith and Philosophy 15 (4): 538-553. 1998.
    In this paper I give a theological foundation to a radical type of virtue ethics I call motivation-based. In motivation-based virtue theory all moral concepts are derivative from the concept of a good motive, the most basic component of a virtue, where what I mean by a motive is an emotion that initiates and directs action towards an end. Here I give a foundation to motivation-based virtue theory by making the motivations of one person in particular the ultimate foundation of all moral value, an…Read more
  •  264
    Morality and religion
    In William J. Wainwright (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Religion, Oxford University Press. 2005.
    Almost all religions contain a code of morality, and in spite of the factthat there are moral codes and philosophies that do not rely upon anyreligion, it has been traditionally argued that there are at least threeimportant ways in which morality needs religion: the goal of the morallife is unreachable without religious practice, religion is necessary toprovide moral motivation, and religion provides morality with itsfoundation and justification. These three ways in which morality may needreligi…Read more
  •  28
    A New Foreknowledge Dilemma
    Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 63 (n/a): 139. 1989.
  •  23
    Rejoinder to Hasker
    Faith and Philosophy 10 (2): 256-260. 1993.
  •  652
    The Uniqueness of Persons
    Journal of Religious Ethics 29 (3). 2001.
    Persons are thought to have a special kind of value, often called "dignity," which, according to Kant, makes them both infinitely valuable and irreplaceably valuable. The author aims to identify what makes a person a person in a way that can explain both aspects of dignity. She considers five definitions of "person": (1) an individual substance of a rational nature (Boethius), (2) a self-conscious being (Locke), (3) a being with the capacity to act for ends (Kant), (4) a being with the capacity …Read more
  •  1
    Ideal agents and ideal observers in epistemology
    In Stephen Hetherington (ed.), Epistemology Futures, Clarendon Press. 2006.
  •  19
    Reported Miracles (review)
    Philosophical Review 105 (4): 538-540. 1996.
    Joseph Houston’s book is a fine contribution to the philosophical investigation of the value of miracle reports for religious apologetics. It covers a wide range of arguments of interest to philosophers about the concept of miracles and the justifiability of belief in their occurrence, but it is also rich in theological and biblical sources. Houston’s reasoning throughout is careful and subtle, but neither technical nor excessively pedantic. So while the book is primarily intended for scholars, …Read more