•  8998
    The inescapability of Gettier problems
    Philosophical Quarterly 44 (174): 65-73. 1994.
  •  284
    When philosophers talk about whether it is reasonable to believe in God, they might take the high intellectual approach of presenting one or more of the traditional arguments for God’s existence, all of which have contemporary forms. Or they might take the opposite approach made popular by some Calvinist philosophers such as Alvin Plantinga who argue that a person can be reasonable in believing something without reasons to support it, and belief in God is like that. There are many beliefs for wh…Read more
  •  20
    Recent work in the philosophy of religion
    Philosophical Books 31 (1): 1-6. 1990.
  •  338
    A Defense of Epistemic Authority
    Res Philosophica 90 (2): 293-306. 2013.
    In this paper I argue that epistemic authority can be justified in the same way as political authority in the tradition of political liberalism. I propose principles of epistemic authority modeled on the general principles of authority proposed by Joseph Raz. These include the Content-Independence thesis, the Pre-emption thesis, the Dependency thesis, and the Normal Justification thesis. The focus is on the authority of a person’s beliefs, although the principles can be applied to the authority …Read more
  •  1195
    Obligation, Good Motives, and the Good (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (2). 2002.
    In Finite and Infinite Goods, Robert Adams brings back a strongly Platonistic form of the metaphysics of value. I applaud most of the theory’s main features: the primacy of the good; the idea that the excellent is more central than the desirable, the derivative status of well-being, the transcendence of the good, the idea that excellence is resemblance to God, the importance of such non-moral goods as beauty, the particularity of persons and their ways of imitating God, and the use of direct ref…Read more
  •  263
    Intellectual virtue: perspectives from ethics and epistemology (edited book)
    with Michael Raymond DePaul
    Oxford University Press. 2003.
    The idea of a virtue has traditionally been important in ethics, but only recently has gained attention as an idea that can explain how we ought to form beliefs as well as how we ought to act. Moral philosophers and epistemologists have different approaches to the idea of intellectual virtue; here, Michael DePaul and Linda Zagzebski bring work from both fields together for the first time to address all of the important issues. It will be required reading for anyone working on either side of the …Read more
  •  32
    Religious Diversity and Social Responsibility
    Logos: A Journal of Catholic Thought and Culture 4 (1): 135-155. 2001.
  •  435
    "What Is Knowledge?"
    In John Greco & Ernest Sosa (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to Epistemology, Oxford: Blackwell. pp. 92-116. 1999.
    Knowledge is a highly valued state in which a person is in cognitive contact with reality. It is, therefore, a relation. On one side of the relation is a conscious subject, and on the other side is a portion of reality to which the knower is directly or indirectly related. While directness is a matter of degree, it is convenient to think of knowledge of things as a direct form of knowledge in comparison to which knowledge about things is indirect. The former has often been called knowledge by ac…Read more
  •  3415
    Emotion and moral judgment
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66 (1). 2003.
    This paper argues that an emotion is a state of affectively perceiving its intentional object as falling under a "thick affective concept" A, a concept that combines cognitive and affective aspects in a way that cannot be pulled apart. For example, in a state of pity an object is seen as pitiful, where to see something as pitiful is to be in a state that is both cognitive and affective. One way of expressing an emotion is to assert that the intentional object of the emotion falls under the thick…Read more
  •  57
    Reply to Professor Zagzebski
    New Scholasticism 58 (4): 460-463. 1984.
  •  912
    The Rule of St. Benedict and Modern Liberal Authority
    European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 2 (1). 2010.
    In this paper I examine the sixth century ’Rule of St. Benedict’, and argue that the authority structure of Benedictine communities as described in that document satisfies well-known principles of authority defended by Joseph Raz. This should lead us to doubt the common assumption that premodern models of authority violate the modern ideal of the autonomy of the self. I suggest that what distinguishes modern liberal authority from Benedictine authority is not the principles that justify it, but …Read more
  •  997
  •  1
    John Martin Fischer, ed., God, Foreknowledge, and Freedom (review)
    Philosophy in Review 10 309-311. 1990.
  •  69
    A Modern Defense of Religious Authority
    Logos: A Journal of Catholic Thought and Culture 19 (3): 15-28. 2016.
  •  189
    Intellectual autonomy
    Philosophical Issues 23 (1): 244-261. 2013.
  •  5
    ``Rejoinder to Hasker"
    Faith and Philosophy 10 (2): 256-260. 1993.
  •  1752
    The Search for the Source of Epistemic Good
    Metaphilosophy 34 (1-2): 12-28. 2003.
    Knowledge has almost always been treated as good, better than mere true belief, but it is remarkably difficult to explain what it is about knowledge that makes it better. I call this “the value problem.” I have previously argued that most forms of reliabilism cannot handle the value problem. In this article I argue that the value problem is more general than a problem for reliabilism, infecting a host of different theories, including some that are internalist. An additional problem is that not a…Read more
  •  3765
    Exemplarist virtue theory
    Metaphilosophy 41 (1-2): 41-57. 1996.
    Abstract: In this essay I outline a radical kind of virtue theory I call exemplarism, which is foundational in structure but which is grounded in exemplars of moral goodness, direct reference to which anchors all the moral concepts in the theory. I compare several different kinds of moral theory by the way they relate the concepts of the good, a right act, and a virtue. In the theory I propose, these concepts, along with the concepts of a duty and of a good life, are defined by reference to exem…Read more
  •  190
    Religious Luck
    Faith and Philosophy 11 (3): 397-413. 1994.
  •  23
    Przedwiedza a wolna wola
    Roczniki Filozoficzne 56 (2): 465-490. 2008.
  •  26
    Virtue in Ethics and Epistemology
    Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 71 1-17. 1997.
  •  2506
    Epistemic Authority and Its Critics
    European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 6 (4): 169--187. 2014.
  •  306
    Omnisubjectivity
    In L. Kvanvig Jonathan (ed.), Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion, Oxford University Press. pp. 231-248. 2013.
  •  576
    The Moral Gap (review)
    Philosophical Review 108 (2): 291-293. 1999.
    The title of Hare’s book refers to the gap between the demand that morality places on us and our natural capacity to live by it. Such a gap is paradoxical if we accept the “‘ought’ implies ‘can”’ principle. The solution, Hare argues, is that the gap is filled by the Christian God. So we ought to be moral and can do so—with divine assistance. Hare’s statement and defense of the existence of the gap combines a rigorously Kantian notion of the moral demand with a rigorously Calvinist notion of huma…Read more
  •  84
    Christian Monotheism
    Faith and Philosophy 6 (1): 3-18. 1989.
    In this paper I present an argument that there can be no more than one God in a way which allows me to give the doctrine ofthe Trinity logical priority over the attributes traditionally used in arguments for God’s unicity. The argument that there is at most one God makes no assumptions about the particular attributes included in divinity. It uses only the Identity of Indiscemibles and a Principle of Plenitude. I then offer a theory on the relationship between individuals and kinds which allows m…Read more
  •  6
    Intellectual motivation and the good of truth
    In Linda Zagzebski & Michael DePaul (eds.), Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives From Ethics and Epistemology, Oxford University Press. pp. 135--154. 2003.