•  16
    Self-Trust and the Diversity of Religions
    Philosophic Exchange 36 (1). 2006.
    The diversity of religions poses two, distinct challenges for belief in a particular religion. The first challenge is based upon an epistemic egalitarianism, according to which all normal human beings are roughly equal in their ability to get knowledge. I argue that this challenge is based on some mistaken assumptions. The second challenge arises from our admiration of people of other faiths. I argue that this second challenge is very serious, since it is rooted in our trust of ourselves.
  • Alan G. Padgett, God, Eternity, and the Nature of Time (review)
    Philosophy in Review 13 179-181. 1993.
  •  68
    Perfect Goodness and Divine Motivation Theory
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 21 (1): 296-309. 1997.
  •  23
    Hermes and Athena: Biblical Exegesis and Philosophical Theology
    Philosophical Books 36 (1): 74-77. 1995.
  • William P. Alston, Perceiving God (review)
    Philosophy in Review 12 75-76. 1992.
  •  88
    Epistemic Value Monism
    In John Greco (ed.), Ernest Sosa and His Critics, Blackwell. 2004.
    This chapter contains section titled: The Value Problem Sosa's Solution Epistemically Valuable False Beliefs Organic Unities Gettier.
  •  37
    Phronesis and Christian Belief
    In G. Bruntrup & R. K. Tacelli (eds.), The Rationality of Theism, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 177--194. 1999.
  •  177
    Virtue in Ethics and Epistemology
    Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 71 1-17. 1997.
  •  150
    Divine Motivation Theory and Exemplarism
    European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 8 (3): 109-121. 2016.
    In this paper I summarize two versions of a new form of ethical theory in which all basic moral terms are defined by direct reference to exemplars of goodness. I call the Christian form Divine Motivation Theory in a book by the same name (Cambridge University Press, 2004), and the more general form I call Exemplarist Virtue Theory (Gifford Lectures 2015) or Exemplarist Moral Theory (forthcoming 2017, Oxford University Press). In the Christian form the supreme exemplar is God. In exemplarist virt…Read more
  •  8974
    The inescapability of Gettier problems
    Philosophical Quarterly 44 (174): 65-73. 1994.
  •  284
    When philosophers talk about whether it is reasonable to believe in God, they might take the high intellectual approach of presenting one or more of the traditional arguments for God’s existence, all of which have contemporary forms. Or they might take the opposite approach made popular by some Calvinist philosophers such as Alvin Plantinga who argue that a person can be reasonable in believing something without reasons to support it, and belief in God is like that. There are many beliefs for wh…Read more
  •  20
    Recent work in the philosophy of religion
    Philosophical Books 31 (1): 1-6. 1990.
  •  337
    A Defense of Epistemic Authority
    Res Philosophica 90 (2): 293-306. 2013.
    In this paper I argue that epistemic authority can be justified in the same way as political authority in the tradition of political liberalism. I propose principles of epistemic authority modeled on the general principles of authority proposed by Joseph Raz. These include the Content-Independence thesis, the Pre-emption thesis, the Dependency thesis, and the Normal Justification thesis. The focus is on the authority of a person’s beliefs, although the principles can be applied to the authority …Read more
  •  1188
    Obligation, Good Motives, and the Good (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (2). 2002.
    In Finite and Infinite Goods, Robert Adams brings back a strongly Platonistic form of the metaphysics of value. I applaud most of the theory’s main features: the primacy of the good; the idea that the excellent is more central than the desirable, the derivative status of well-being, the transcendence of the good, the idea that excellence is resemblance to God, the importance of such non-moral goods as beauty, the particularity of persons and their ways of imitating God, and the use of direct ref…Read more
  •  263
    Intellectual virtue: perspectives from ethics and epistemology (edited book)
    with Michael Raymond DePaul
    Oxford University Press. 2003.
    The idea of a virtue has traditionally been important in ethics, but only recently has gained attention as an idea that can explain how we ought to form beliefs as well as how we ought to act. Moral philosophers and epistemologists have different approaches to the idea of intellectual virtue; here, Michael DePaul and Linda Zagzebski bring work from both fields together for the first time to address all of the important issues. It will be required reading for anyone working on either side of the …Read more
  •  32
    Religious Diversity and Social Responsibility
    Logos: A Journal of Catholic Thought and Culture 4 (1): 135-155. 2001.
  •  430
    "What Is Knowledge?"
    In John Greco & Ernest Sosa (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to Epistemology, Oxford: Blackwell. pp. 92-116. 1999.
    Knowledge is a highly valued state in which a person is in cognitive contact with reality. It is, therefore, a relation. On one side of the relation is a conscious subject, and on the other side is a portion of reality to which the knower is directly or indirectly related. While directness is a matter of degree, it is convenient to think of knowledge of things as a direct form of knowledge in comparison to which knowledge about things is indirect. The former has often been called knowledge by ac…Read more
  •  3410
    Emotion and moral judgment
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66 (1). 2003.
    This paper argues that an emotion is a state of affectively perceiving its intentional object as falling under a "thick affective concept" A, a concept that combines cognitive and affective aspects in a way that cannot be pulled apart. For example, in a state of pity an object is seen as pitiful, where to see something as pitiful is to be in a state that is both cognitive and affective. One way of expressing an emotion is to assert that the intentional object of the emotion falls under the thick…Read more
  •  57
    Reply to Professor Zagzebski
    New Scholasticism 58 (4): 460-463. 1984.
  •  904
    The Rule of St. Benedict and Modern Liberal Authority
    European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 2 (1). 2010.
    In this paper I examine the sixth century ’Rule of St. Benedict’, and argue that the authority structure of Benedictine communities as described in that document satisfies well-known principles of authority defended by Joseph Raz. This should lead us to doubt the common assumption that premodern models of authority violate the modern ideal of the autonomy of the self. I suggest that what distinguishes modern liberal authority from Benedictine authority is not the principles that justify it, but …Read more
  •  992
  •  1
    John Martin Fischer, ed., God, Foreknowledge, and Freedom (review)
    Philosophy in Review 10 309-311. 1990.
  •  69
    A Modern Defense of Religious Authority
    Logos: A Journal of Catholic Thought and Culture 19 (3): 15-28. 2016.