•  102
    Authority and responsibility in international criminal law
    In Samantha Besson & John Tasioulas (eds.), The philosophy of international law, Oxford University Press. pp. 589-604. 2010.
  •  1
    III*—Socratic Suicide?
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 83 (1): 35-48. 1983.
    R. A. Duff; III*—Socratic Suicide?, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 83, Issue 1, 1 June 1983, Pages 35–48, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/
  •  3
    The Value of Life
    Philosophical Books 27 (4): 241-243. 1986.
  •  5
    Harm to Others
    Philosophical Books 27 (1): 54-56. 1986.
  •  8
    Socratic Suicide?
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 83. 1983.
    R. A. Duff; III*—Socratic Suicide?, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 83, Issue 1, 1 June 1983, Pages 35–48, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/
  •  15
    David B. Wong, "Moral Relativity" (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 36 (42): 99. 1986.
  •  318
    Rule Violations and Wrongdoings
    In Stephen Shute & Andrew Simester (eds.), Criminal Law Theory: Doctrines of the General Part, Oxford University Press. pp. 47--74. 2002.
  •  30
    Criminal responsibility and public reason
    In Michael D. A. Freeman & Ross Harrison (eds.), Law and Philosophy, Oxford University Press. 2007.
  •  62
    Punishment and the Duties of Offenders
    Law and Philosophy 32 (1): 109-127. 2013.
    A critical discussion of Victor Tadros, The Ends of Harm.
  •  33
    Why Punish?
    Cogito 6 (2): 109-110. 1992.
  •  39
    Law, Language and Community: Some Preconditions of Criminal Liability
    Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 18 (2): 189-206. 1998.
    We can usefully distinguish the conditions of criminal liability (those conditions which must be satisfied if a defendant is to be duly convicted, with which a criminal trial is concerned) from its preconditions (those conditions which must be satisfied if the trial, as a process which aims to determine whether or not this person is criminally liable, is to be legitimate at all). Some of these preconditions concern the defendant's status as a rsponsible citizen, who can properly be called to ans…Read more
  •  110
    Iv-answering for crime
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 106 (1): 87-113. 2006.
    We can gain fresh insights into aspects of criminal liability by focusing first on the prior topic of criminal responsibility, and on the relational dimensions of responsibility: responsibility is responsibility for something, to someone. We are criminally responsible as citizens, to our fellow citizens, for committing 'public' wrongs: I discuss the difficulty of giving determinate content to this idea of public wrongs, and the way in which, whereas moral responsibility is typically strict, crim…Read more
  •  38
    Theorizing Criminal Law: a 25th Anniversary Essay
    Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 25 (3): 353-367. 2005.
  •  13
    Good and Evil and the Criminal Law
    In Christopher Donald Cordner (ed.), Philosophy, Ethics and a Common Humanity, Routledge. pp. 68-81. 2011.
  •  60
    Camus and Rebellion: From Solipsism to Morality
    Philosophical Investigations 5 (2): 116-134. 1982.
  •  3
    Book Review (review)
    Law and Philosophy 31 (6): 753-758. 2012.
  •  9
    No Title available: New Books (review)
    Philosophy 59 (230): 541-542. 1984.
  •  35
    Virtue, Vice and the Criminal Law - A Response to Huigens and Yankah
    In H. H. Lai & A. Amaya (eds.), Law, Virtue and Justice, Hart Publishing. pp. 195-214. 2013.
    First paragraph: It is worth distinguishing two kinds of role that ideas of virtue and vice might play in the criminal law (or in our theoretical understanding of the criminal law). Each kind admits of a range of variations; each can be more or less ambitious in scope and aim: but although there are of course quite close connections between the two kinds, we can usefully sketch them as two different ways of developing a virtue jurisprudence of criminal law. Both kinds of role are connected to vi…Read more
  •  22
    Attempted Homicide
    Legal Theory 1 (2): 149-178. 1995.
    Criminal attempts, it is often said, are crimes of intention. While many complete crimes can be committed recklessly, criminal attempts require “purposive conduct”; in attempts “the intent is the essence of the crime.” But what kind of intention is required; what must be intended, or purposed, by someone who is to be guilty of a criminal attempt?
  •  3
    Irrationality and criminal responsibility
    Philosophical Books 22 (1): 1-8. 1981.
  •  226
    Towards a Modest Legal Moralism
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 8 (1): 217-235. 2014.
    After distinguishing different species of Legal Moralism I outline and defend a modest, positive Legal Moralism, according to which we have good reason to criminalize some type of conduct if it constitutes a public wrong. Some of the central elements of the argument will be: the need to remember that the criminal law is a political, not a moral practice, and therefore that in asking what kinds of conduct we have good reason to criminalize, we must begin not with the entire realm of wrongdoing, b…Read more
  •  23
    Defining Crimes: Essays on the Special Part of the Criminal Law (edited book)
    Oxford University Press UK. 2005.
    This collection of original essays, by some of the best known contemporary criminal law theorists, tackles a range of issues about the criminal law's 'special part' - the part of the criminal law that defines specific offences. One of its aims is to show the importance, for theory as well as for practice, of focusing on the special part as well as on the general part which usually receives much more theoretical attention. Some of the issues covered concern the proper scope of the criminal law, f…Read more
  •  18
    Responsibility, citizenship, and criminal law
    In Antony Duff & Stuart P. Green (eds.), Philosophical Foundations of Criminal Law, Oxford University Press. pp. 125--148. 2011.