•  74
    The Intrusion of Mercy
    Ohio State Journal of Criminal Law 4 361-87. 2007.
    On the basis of a communicative theory of criminal punishment, I show how mercy has a significant but limited role to play in the criminal law—in particular (although not only) in criminal sentencing. Mercy involves an intrusion into the realm of criminal law of values and concerns that are not themselves part of the perspective of criminal law: a merciful sentencer acts beyond the limits of her legal role, on the basis of moral considerations that conflict with the demands of penal justice. Som…Read more
  •  7
    Iv*-answering for crime
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 106 (1): 85-111. 2006.
  •  8
    Symposium on Criminalization
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 8 (1): 147-148. 2014.
  •  208
    Guiding Commitments and Criminal Liability for Attempts
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 6 (3): 411-427. 2012.
    A critical discussion of Gideon Yaffe's "guiding commitment" account of attempts, with special reference to attempts in the criminal law.
  •  21
    Philosophical Foundations of Criminal Law (edited book)
    Oxford University Press UK. 2011.
    25 leading contemporary theorists of criminal law tackle a range of foundational issues about the proper aims and structure of the criminal law in a liberal democracy. The challenges facing criminal law are many. There are crises of over-criminalization and over-imprisonment; penal policy has become so politicized that it is difficult to find any clear consensus on what aims the criminal law can properly serve; governments seeking to protect their citizens in the face of a range of perceived thr…Read more
  •  1
    C.L. Ten, Crime, Guilt, And Punishment (review)
    Philosophy in Review 8 325-327. 1988.
  • Punishment
    In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The Oxford handbook of practical ethics, Oxford University Press. 2003.
  •  13
    What kind of responsibility must criminal law presuppose?
    In Richard Swinburne (ed.), Free Will and Modern Science, Oup/british Academy. 2011.
    This chapter argues that the kind of responsibility that we must have, if the enterprise of criminal law and punishment is to be consistent with the demands of justice, is something much more modest, much less metaphysically ambitious, than the ‘ultimate’ responsibility that Strawson so persuasively denies in Chapter 8. If we are to be clear about the kind of responsibility that is relevant to criminal law, we must first be clear about the criminal law itself — about the kind of enterprise that …Read more
  •  16
    Lawrence A. Blum, "Friendship, Altruism and Morality" (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 32 (27): 181. 1982.
  •  48
    Trials and Punishments
    Cambridge University Press. 1986.
    How can a system of criminal punishment be justified? In particular can it be justified if the moral demand that we respect each other as autonomous moral agents is taken seriously? Traditional attempts to justify punishment as a deterrent or as retribution fail, but Duff suggests that punishment can be understood as a communicative attempt to bring a wrong-doer to repent her crime. This account is supported by discussions of moral blame, of penance, of the nature of the law's demands, and of th…Read more
  •  40
    Relational Reasons and the Criminal Law
    In B. Leiter & L. Green (eds.), Oxford Studies in Legal Philosophy, vol. 2, Oxford Up. pp. 175-208. 2013.
    First paragraph: Some reasons for action are relational. I have a relational reason to Φ when I have reason to Φ in virtue of a relationship in which I stand, or a role that I fill; absent that relationship or that role I would not have that reason to Φ ; others who do not stand in that relationship or fill that role do not have that reason to Φ . I have a relational reason to feed this child -- that he is my child: absent that parental relationship, I might still have a reason to feed him, as m…Read more
  •  15
    Freewill and Responsibility (review)
    Philosophical Books 21 (1): 52-54. 1980.
  •  383
    Part of the Studies in Crime and Public Policy series, this book, written by one of the top philosophers of punishment, examines the main trends in penal theorizing over the past three decades. Duff asks what can justify criminal punishment, and then explores the legitimacy of actual practices by examining what would count as adequate justification for them. Duff argues that a "communicative conception of punishment," which he presents as a third way between consequentialist and retributive theo…Read more
  •  63
    Criminal Responsibility and the Emotions: If Fear and Anger Can Exculpate, Why Not Compassion?
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 58 (2): 189-220. 2015.
    The article offers an Aristotelian analysis of emotion-based defences in criminal law: someone who commits an offence is entitled to an excuse if she was motivated by a justifiably aroused and strongly felt emotion that gave her good reason to commit the offence and that might have destabilised the practical rationality even of a ‘reasonable’ person. This analysis captures the logical structure of duress and provocation as excuses—and also shows why provocation is controversial as even a partial…Read more
  •  52
    Mercy
    In John Deigh & David Dolinko (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of the Criminal Law, Oxford University Press. 2011.
  •  182
    Punishment and Crime
    with Ross Harrison
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 62 139-167. 1988.
  •  9
    Book reviews (review)
    Mind 104 (413): 211-214. 1995.
  •  10
    Action and Criminal Responsibility
    In O'Connor & C. Sandis (eds.), Blackwell Companion to the Philosophy of Action, Blackwell. pp. 331-7. 2010.
  •  130
    Intentionally Killing the Innocent
    Analysis 34 (1). 1973.
  •  98
    Strict responsibility, moral and criminal
    Journal of Value Inquiry 43 (3): 295-313. 2009.
  • HUTCHINSON, D. S. The Virtues of Aristotle (review)
    Philosophy 62 (n/a): 539. 1987.
  •  39
    Philosophy and 'the life of the law'
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 26 (3): 245-258. 2009.
    abstract Focusing on the criminal law, I discuss three ways in which analytical philosophers might contribute to the development or health of the law (and of legal theory). The first is as humble under-labourers, who seek only to clarify legal rules and doctrines, but not to criticise them. This modest conception of the role of philosophy, however, proves to be untenable: clarification must become rational reconstruction — an attempt to make rational sense of the law; and rational reconstruction…Read more