•  15
    Reviews (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34 (3): 312-313. 1983.
  •  50
    Uncertainty and vagueness/imprecision are not the same: one can be certain about events described using vague predicates and about imprecisely specified events, just as one can be uncertain about precisely specified events. Exactly because of this, a question arises about how one ought to assign probabilities to imprecisely specified events in the case when no possible available evidence will eradicate the imprecision (because, say, of the limits of accuracy of a measuring device). Modelling imp…Read more
  •  113
    Log[p(h/eb)/p(h/b)] is the one true measure of confirmation
    Philosophy of Science 63 (1): 21-26. 1996.
    Plausibly, when we adopt a probabilistic standpoint any measure Cb of the degree to which evidence e confirms hypothesis h relative to background knowledge b should meet these five desiderata: Cb > 0 when P > P < 0 when P < P; Cb = 0 when P = P. Cb is some function of the values P and P assume on the at most sixteen truth-functional combinations of e and h. If P < P and P = P then Cb ≤ Cb; if P = P and P < P then Cb ≥ Cb. Cb – Cb is fully determined by Cb and Cbe – Cbe; if Cb = 0 then Cb + Cbe =…Read more
  •  215
    What is the Normative Role of Logic?
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 83 (1): 269-298. 2009.
    In making assertions one takes on commitments to the consistency of what one asserts and to the logical consequences of what one asserts. Although there is no quick link between belief and assertion, the dialectical requirements on assertion feed back into normative constraints on those beliefs that constitute one's evidence. But if we are not certain of many of our beliefs and that uncertainty is modelled in terms of probabilities, then there is at least prima facie incoherence between the norm…Read more
  •  22
    Ron Bontekoe
    with Modal Metaphysics
    International Philosophical Quarterly 32 (2). 1992.
  •  79
    The foundations of probability and quantum mechanics
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 22 (2). 1993.
    Taking as starting point two familiar interpretations of probability, we develop these in a perhaps unfamiliar way to arrive ultimately at an improbable claim concerning the proper axiomatization of probability theory: the domain of definition of a point-valued probability distribution is an orthomodular partially ordered set. Similar claims have been made in the light of quantum mechanics but here the motivation is intrinsically probabilistic. This being so the main task is to investigate what …Read more
  •  46
    Disjunction and Disjunctive Syllogism
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 28 (1). 1998.
    The validity of argument by disjunctive syllogism has been denied by proponents of relevant and paraconsistent logic. DS is stigmatised for its role in inferences — most notably C.I. Lewis's derivation of that fallacy of irrelevance ex falso quodlibet — that involve both it and other rules of inference governing disjunction, or, to speak more precisely, other rules of inference taken to apply to the very same disjunction that obeys DS. In avoiding these inferences the road less travelled is to d…Read more
  •  27
    Reply to Currie
    Mind 97 (387): 457-460. 1988.
  •  25
    From Introduction: In a 1968 article, ‘Probability Measures of Fuzzy Events’, Lotfi Zadeh pro-posed accounts of absolute and conditional probability for fuzzy sets (Zadeh, 1968)
  •  89
    Physical probabilities
    Synthese 73 (2). 1987.
    A conception of probability as an irreducible feature of the physical world is outlined. Propensity analyses of probability are examined and rejected as both formally and conceptually inadequate. It is argued that probability is a non-dispositional property of trial-types; probabilities are attributed to outcomes as event-types. Brier's Rule in an objectivist guise is used to forge a connection between physical and subjective probabilities. In the light of this connection there are grounds for s…Read more
  •  79
    A note on scale invariance
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34 (1): 49-55. 1983.
    A note on scale invariance.
  •  209
    Not every truth has a truthmaker II
    Analysis 73 (3): 473-481. 2013.
    A proof employing no semantic terms is offered in support of the claim that there can be truths without truthmakers. The logical resources used in the proof are weak but do include the structural rule Contraction
  •  58
    On the completeness of non-philonian stoic logic
    History and Philosophy of Logic 16 (1): 39-64. 1995.
    The majority of formal accounts attribute to Stoic logicians the classical truth-functional understanding of the material conditional and exclusive disjunction.These interpretations were disputed,...
  •  54
    Is there a logic of confirmation transfer?
    Erkenntnis 53 (3): 309-335. 2000.
    This article begins by exploring a lost topic in the philosophy of science:the properties of the relations evidence confirming h confirmsh'' and, more generally, evidence confirming each ofh1, h2, ..., hm confirms at least one of h1, h2,ldots;, hn''.The Bayesian understanding of confirmation as positive evidential relevanceis employed throughout. The resulting formal system is, to say the least, oddlybehaved. Some aspects of this odd behaviour the system has in common withsome of the non-classic…Read more
  •  217
    The thesis that, in a system of natural deduction, the meaning of a logical constant is given by some or all of its introduction and elimination rules has been developed recently in the work of Dummett, Prawitz, Tennant, and others, by the addition of harmony constraints. Introduction and elimination rules for a logical constant must be in harmony. By deploying harmony constraints, these authors have arrived at logics no stronger than intuitionist propositional logic. Classical logic, they maint…Read more
  •  5
    Reviews (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 35 (1): 312-313. 1984.
  •  152
    Bruno de finetti and the logic of conditional events
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48 (2): 195-232. 1997.
    This article begins by outlining some of the history—beginning with brief remarks of Quine's—of work on conditional assertions and conditional events. The upshot of the historical narrative is that diverse works from various starting points have circled around a nexus of ideas without convincingly tying them together. Section 3 shows how ideas contained in a neglected article of de Finetti's lead to a unified treatment of the topics based on the identification of conditional events as the object…Read more
  •  234
    On Gödel Sentences and What They Say
    Philosophia Mathematica 15 (2): 193-226. 2007.
    Proofs of Gödel's First Incompleteness Theorem are often accompanied by claims such as that the gödel sentence constructed in the course of the proof says of itself that it is unprovable and that it is true. The validity of such claims depends closely on how the sentence is constructed. Only by tightly constraining the means of construction can one obtain gödel sentences of which it is correct, without further ado, to say that they say of themselves that they are unprovable and that they are tru…Read more
  •  27
    Annabel and the bookmaker: An everyday tale of bayesian folk
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 69 (1). 1991.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  14
    Languages of Possibility: An essay in Philosophical Logic
    Philosophical Books 31 (4): 222-224. 1992.
  •  4
    Review of Ralph Charles Sutherland Walker: Kant: the arguments of the philosophers (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34 (3): 312-313. 1983.
  •  101
    While there is now considerable experimental evidence that, on the one hand, participants assign to the indicative conditional as probability the conditional probability of consequent given antecedent and, on the other, they assign to the indicative conditional the “defective truth-table” in which a conditional with false antecedent is deemed neither true nor false, these findings do not in themselves establish which multi-premise inferences involving conditionals participants endorse. A natural…Read more
  •  155
    Tarski on truth and its definition
    In Timothy Childers, Petr Kolft & Vladimir Svoboda (eds.), Logica '96: Proceedings of the 10th International Symposium, Filosofia. pp. 198-210. 1997.
    Of his numerous investigations ... Tarski was most proud of two: his work on truth and his design of an algorithm in 1930 to decide the truth or falsity of any sentence of the elementary theory of the high school Euclidean geometry. [...] His mathematical treatment of the semantics of languages and the concept of truth has had revolutionary consequences for mathematics, linguistics, and philosophy, and Tarski is widely thought of as the man who "defined truth". The seeming simplicity of his famo…Read more